Hoppe claims that a consistent empiricist would seek "to establish the
theorem of Pythagoras by actually measuring sides and angles of
triangles. Just as anyone would have to comment on such an endeavor,
mustn't we say that to think economic propositions would have to be
empirically tested is a sign of outright intellectual confusion?"
("Praxeology and Economic Science: Sec. I"). The empirical testing of
the Pythagorean theorem would be absurd because Euclidean geometry is
both a priori true and remarkably successful: its insights can be
perfectly applied to engineering and construction. The validity of
geometry, too, follows from the existence of human action, since
"[a]ction is the employment of a physical body in space" (Hoppe,
"Praxeology and Economic Science: Sec. II"). The ultimate standard of
measurement is the manner in which the human body exists and moves
spatially. These positions and movements can be analyzed in terms of
simpler components: points, lines, and planes. To measure these
spatial properties, humans can create instruments on the basis of the
ubiquitously known manner in which the body exists and moves in order
to act. No specific measurement or observation can ever refute the
validity of Euclidean standards of measurement: the standards are what
make measurement itself possible. Euclidean geometry "is not only the
very precondition for any empirical spatial description, it is also
the precondition for any active orientation in space" (Hoppe, "On
Praxeology and the Praxeological Foundations of Epistemology: Sec.
III"). If the standards of Euclidean geometry were not valid and
perfectly accurate in describing reality, the human body as a
three-dimensional entity would not be able to exist and relate to
other three-dimensional entities.
The axioms of Euclidean geometry correspond to the physical world,
whereas the axioms of geometric systems contrary to Euclid's do not.
(That is, they are not true axioms, since they can be elementarily
refuted in the course of ubiquitous daily observation.) The human body
can be measured by using three and only three spatial parameters
known as dimensions: any system of measurement claiming more or less
than three dimensions will fail to adequately describe man's physical
form. All parts of the human body have boundaries, describing which
necessitates the Euclidean constructs of points, lines, and planes.
Furthermore, all human movement and interaction with other entities
occurs three-dimensionally. Every possible path of motion can be
described by adding three mutually perpendicular vectors of the proper
magnitudes. Moreover, all spatial measuring instruments can only be
built with Euclidean postulates at the foundation of their design:
Euclidean geometry
is
no more and no less than the reconstruction of the ideal norms
underlying our construction of such homogeneous basic forms as
points, lines, planes and distances, which are in a more or less
perfect but always perfectible way incorporated or realized in
even our most primitive instruments of spatial measurements such
as a measuring rod. (Hoppe, "On Praxeology and the Praxeological
Foundations of Epistemology: Sec. III") |
No measurement can ever refute the validity of
Euclidean geometry, since measuring tools themselves as well as the
bodies and movements of those who measure are predicated upon the
axioms of Euclid's system. If the spatial qualities of humans and
all the objects they observe and interact with can be described
and measured only through Euclid's system, there is no point in
asserting that any non-Euclidean geometry can also be true: it cannot
be true if it describes nothing that exists!
Empiricism denies the possibility of certain knowledge because it
ignores the existence of human action. Empiricists systematically
deride the valid and empirically successful branches of a
priori knowledge praxeology, logic, arithmetic, and Euclidean
geometry as meaningless formalisms devoid of actual information
about reality. In so doing, the empiricists implicitly erect an
impregnable barrier between the mind and reality. According to them,
if X is a fact of reality, it cannot be conclusively grasped by the
mind; if X was derived by the mind, it cannot be relevant to reality.
The empiricists can claim this only by evading man's identity as an
acting being with a mind that exists and acts in reality. The mind of
an agent in reality must necessarily have access to the
external world and the capacity to comprehend existence by means of
reason. This access implies the mind's ability to derive certain,
irrefutable, unfalsifiable knowledge about its own nature and the
nature of the world with which it interacts.
Refutation of Historicism |
The insights of praxeology allow us to disprove
another doctrine that denies the possibility of certain, objective
economic knowledge: historicism. Hoppe describes historicism as the
belief that economic events "are subjective expressions and
interpretations unfolding in history to be understood and interpreted
by the economist just as a literary text unfolds before and is
interpreted by its reader" (Hoppe, "Praxeology and Economic Science:
Sec. II"). To the historicist, no absolute, universal economic laws
exist. All that exists is a set of past economic data as incorporated
into historical texts. No past economic event occurred because it
necessarily had to as derived from insights into the nature of
human action but rather the events happened simply because they did.
What is true for one historical era might not be true for another. The
free market, according to the historicists, might have worked in the
19th century, but it does not necessarily have to work today nor
would even basic economic principles, such as the law of diminishing
marginal utility, have to be permanent, immutable, or universally
applicable. To the historicist, there is not only no certain knowledge
about the economic principles behind historical events there is also
no certain knowledge even about what historical events actually
happened. Since historical economic events are not constrained by
any universally valid laws, there is no way to objectively interpret
and gain genuine knowledge from them:
[T]he formation of these
always contingently related human expressions and their
interpretations is also not constrained by any objective law
[H]istorical and economic events are whatever someone expresses or
interprets them to be, and their description by the historian and
economist is then whatever he expresses or interprets these past
subjective events to have been. (Hoppe, "On Praxeology and the
Praxeological Foundations of Epistemology: Sec. II") |
To the historicist, both history and economics
ultimately become whatever a given historian or economist chooses to
turn them into, with no definitive criterion of truth and falsity to
verify or disprove a given economic theory. Mises was perhaps too
generous to write that "[h]istoricism aim[s] at replacing [economics]
by economic history
" (4). Rather, historicism replaces both
economics and history with the historicist's unsubstantiated
wishes concerning what each discipline ought to have been.
Hoppe describes the unscientific result: the historicist's "output
takes on the form of disquisitions on what someone feels about what he
feels was felt by somebody else" ("On Praxeology and the Praxeological
Foundations of Epistemology: Sec. II").
The fundamental premise of historicism can be refuted in a similar
manner to the fundamental premise of empiricism. Historicism claims
that there are no permanent, constant economic laws transcending a
given era and location. That premise itself, however, is held by the
historicists to be a constant and time-invariant relation. That is, we
cannot say of any era and location that its economic events
follow a universally applicable, logically deducible set of laws. The
historicist is faced with two alternatives. Either he admits that his
basic premise constitutes a time-invariant relation, whereby he
implicitly rejects historicism's blanket denial of such relations and
concedes the possibility of a priori, logical, universally valid
economics. Or he denies that this premise is a time-invariant
relation, which means that we can never ascertain its absolute
truth. Historicism can be true for one era, but not for another
and does not have to be true for any era. Hoppe describes the
sorry state the historicist premise would attain under such an
assumption: "it may be true now, if we wish it so, yet possibly false
a moment later, in case we do not, with no one ever knowing anything
about whether we do or do not" ("On Praxeology and the Praxeological
Foundations of Epistemology: Sec. II"). If the historicist premise
under a consistent application of historicism can possibly be false,
that, too, leaves open the possibility of using logical, a priori
methods for arriving at economic truths.
Moreover, the analysis of historical data alone is sufficient in
obtaining any understanding of economics. According to Hoppe,
"observational evidence can only reveal things as they happen to be;
there is nothing in it that would indicate why things must be
the way they are" ("On Praxeology and the Praxeological Foundations of
Epistemology: Sec. II"). When we examine a succession of economic
statistics or an account of who traded with whom or what government
policies correlated with what effects on industry we only know
that given events happened. We cannot, from sheer observation
know why they happened; we cannot have any comprehensive
understanding of causality, since causality is a category of action.
All we can effectively understand from observing historical data alone
is what physical movements individuals happened to make in a given
time and place. In order to form any meaningful theory that
accurately interprets the historical events, man must
introspect and reflect upon those events using the methods
available to his rational faculty. There is no way to interpret
historical events if one conceives of them as mere meaningless,
contingent physical movements. The movements must be analyzed within
the framework of action: the economist knows that the events
are actions because he, too, is an acting being, and his mind is
linked to reality via his status as such. As soon as one concedes that
historical events are actions, the entire body of propositions
derivable from that fact indeed, the whole science of praxeology
can be applied to them.
Only the logical, a priori methods of praxeology can reveal any
meaning to historical economic events. For example, let us presume
that in year X the government of a country set an artificial ceiling
on the price of widgets. A shortage of widgets occurred. However, in
year Y, the government established a similar ceiling and no shortage
took place. The historicist would hasten to claim that we cannot know
with certainty that government price ceilings have negative effects:
after all, in year Y, no shortage happened. Only the methods of
praxeology could show the historicist that a government price ceiling
is always detrimental under a given set of conditions namely,
when the government tries to restrict a good's price below the market
equilibrium.
The praxeologist would know that the widget shortage did not occur
only because of the positive influence of some other factor
beside the price ceiling. In year Y, the widget manufacturers'
technological capacity increased independent of government
regulation to enable them to mass-produce widgets on a scale
previously impossible. The shift in technological capacity happened to
occur at the same time as the government was in the process of
imposing its price ceiling. However, because of the increased supply
of widgets from mass production, the equilibrium price of widgets was
pushed below the government price ceiling; hence, the
restriction was plainly irrelevant to the widget price: it was
tantamount to the government forbidding anyone to charge more than
$500 for a bottle of milk. This particular historical event does not
negate the universal truth that, whenever the government artificially
pushes a good's price below market equilibrium, shortages will
result since the number of goods consumers demand at the lower price
will exceed the number of goods producers are willing to supply at
that price. The praxeological insight concerning the origin of
shortages does not require the analysis of an open set of historical
data in order to be validated with certainty; all one needs to know is
the nature of supply, demand, and market equilibrium arrived at via
the action axiom. However, once understood, the praxeological truth
can be applied to any relevant historical event and give the
economist certain, irrefutable knowledge about it. Unlike historicism,
which seeks to negate the objective truth of both economics and
history, praxeology renders the study of both disciplines meaningful
and crucial to man's understanding of reality.
We have demonstrated how praxeology the science of
human action affirms the validity of an entire type of human
knowledge synthetic a priori truths without which cognition of
reality would be unattainable. The action axiom, the starting point of
praxeology, is also an indispensable link between reason and
observation, for humans have the minds of entities acting in the
absolute reality. By means of the insight that humans act, the study
of an entire array of disciplines logic, epistemology, arithmetic,
geometry, economics, and history (when analyzed with the help of
praxeology) can be demonstrated as useful and capable of imparting
certain, irrefutable, unfalsifiable knowledge. Furthermore, two
principal doctrines empiricism and historicism which deny the
possibility of irrefutable knowledge have been shown to be false,
contradictory, and absurd. The logical errors in both doctrines
implicitly concede the possibility and validity of a priori economic
analysis and a priori knowledge in general.
|