Buchanan explains that the unanimity principle does not have
to apply to the stage of post-constitutional operations of
the government established by the constitution. The level of
routine government operations takes place under the
constitutional process rules that are meant to apply to
every individual situation. Buchanan says that rational
contractors will unanimously agree to less than unanimity
rules which reduce decision making costs with respect to
routine collective decisions. Obtaining unanimous consent is
too costly so the framers set up a legislative process by
which the original distribution of property rights could be
changed in order to create otherwise unattainable public
goods.
According to Buchanan, people have agreed to
majority voting because they expect to be more often in a winning
coalition than in a losing coalition. Individuals within the political
sector base their choices and coalition memberships on their personal
evaluation of costs and benefits. He notes that majority coalitions
tend to be unstable, temporary, and ever-changing. Majority rule is
apt to lead to inefficient outcomes such as the overprovision of
collectively supplied goods and services and majority cost-shifting of
some of the costs onto the minority. These are the allocative effects
of majority rule. Buchanan observes that when redistribution occurs
individuals are no longer functioning under a veil of ignorance.
Majority-voting rules permit a multitude of separate potential
coalitions to put forth taxing and spending proposals. At the
post-constitutional stage a losing minority cannot legitimately claim
that they were forced by the majority. Buchanan explains that
government compulsion with respect to the supply of public goods is
legitimate if the original contract (i.e., the constitution) is the
product of an effective unanimity rule. Decisions regarding the
financing of collective projects are regarded as the outcome of
voluntary agreements among citizens. Political voting mechanisms thus
serve as substitutes for decentralized private decisions where
opportunities (for public goods) exist that cannot be easily embodied
in private contracts.
Post-Constitutional Analysis |
Politics consists mainly of individual and group
attempts to obtain the most benefits from government and to pay the
least amount of taxes. According to Buchanan, post-constitutional
analysis involves the examination of strategies players adopt within
defined constitutional rules and principles. During the
post-constitutional stage players treat the rules of the game as
constraints and devise strategies to deal with them. Today, most
government taxation and spending policy is dictated by pressure groups
acting in their own perceived special interests and not by politicians
acting in the public interest.
Buchanan distinguishes between the protective state and the productive
state which has "evolved" into the redistributive state. He says that
what we generally consider to be a "limited" state actually includes
more than merely the protective and judicial services associated with
the "night watchman" state – it also includes the productive state
which furnishes public goods such as roads and schools. The protective
state enforces agreed-to rights and the productive state produces
collective goods. The protective state enforces neutral, unanimously
agreed upon law. In turn, the productive state may operate through
rules of less than unanimity given that at the constitutional stage
those rules find unanimous agreement. Whereas the protective state
functions in an objective fashion to determine rule infractions, the
actions of the productive state are subject to choice. Buchanan's
economic theory of the origins of law is consistent with the state
provision of public goods. When the protective state was set up, the
consenting persons discerned that public goods in the future may be
wanted and that without a productive state many public goods would be
unobtainable. The framers realized that there would be difficulties
financing projects because anyone can use such services without
contributing financially.
The modern state is transforming into the illiberal and
redistributionist state as the productive state does not simply
provide public goods but also intervenes in the private economy by
promoting the same ends pursued in the private sector. The government
has taken over many functions previously left to markets. With no
meaningful distinction between public and private interests, people
dissatisfied with their results in the private sector will
increasingly turn to the public sector. Coalitions of voters seek
special advantages from the state to obtain legislation favorable to
them. Buchanan explains that looking to the government to remedy
things can lead to more harm than good.
Much of today's politics can be viewed as rent-seeking activity (e.g.,
pork barrel politics). A rent-seeking society leads to the
redistributive state that transfers wealth from one party to another
through collective action. If there is value to be gained through the
political process, people will invest time and resources in their
attempts to capture this value for themselves. The emergence of the
welfare state and the growth of government have increased
opportunities for, and rewards of, redistributive activities. Interest
groups in a rent-seeking society will make efforts to gain their own
benefits at the expense of others through the use of government. More
and more, individuals are investing in rent-seeking and rent
protection.
The Public Choice application of the logic of microeconomics to
politics has revealed the prevalence of rent-seeking and free riding
on the part of voters, politicians, bureaucrats, and the recipients of
public monies. With costs spread over the taxpayers at large,
individuals with concentrated interests in increased government
expenditures (as benefits) take a free ride on people with diffuse
interests in lower taxes. This reflects the logic of concentrated
benefits and dispersed costs. Politics produces a policy mix which
affords short term and easily identified benefits at the expense of
largely hidden and long term costs. The resulting cost shifting leads
to the overprovision of government goods and services as majority
voting rules allow for many separate coalitions. When factions
dominate the voting process, projects tend to be funded that cannot be
justified on an aggregate cost-benefit basis. Value taken in the form
of such transfers make the investment wasteful in an overall sense.
Politicians and Public Servants |
What about the behavior of politicians, legislators,
and bureaucrats? Buchanan explains that problems are exacerbated by
the rational, self-interested behavior of such individuals. He
contends that when people enter government they act on the same
motives as when they are agents in the private sector. It follows that
bureaucrats want to maximize their budgets thereby obtaining greater
power, larger salaries, and so on. Government officials make choices
based on their self-interest thereby generating pressure for higher
taxes, bigger budgets, more regulations, and more power. Politicians
act, at least to a certain extent, out of self-interest and will
attempt to gain as many votes as possible to reach positions of power
and to receive larger budget allocations.
Public Choice studies the behavior of politicians and bureaucrats in a
representative democracy like we have in the United States. Before
Public Choice, economists assumed an objective welfare function which
government officials sought to maximize and thought that political
agents were inspired to pursue that objective welfare function. The
assumption was that nobody in government maximized for himself –
there was only the public good. Buchanan understood that political
decision makers are not necessarily seekers of the public good but
instead they are interested players who trade to their own advantages
such as increased power and reelection. He says that people do not
change when they take an oath of office or when they join a government
agency.
Politicians, bureaucrats, and other public servants may say that they
are devoted to the public interest, common good, general welfare, or
social justice, or that they act from some altruistic motivation, but
Buchanan maintains that public officials are not motivated by
disinterested service to the public and that they, like everyone else,
endeavor to maximize their own utilities. It is in the interest of
political representatives to spend and say to their constituents that
they voted for the benefit of their community. The result is
competition between politicians for constituency support through the
use of promises of discriminatory transfers of wealth. Bureaucracies
tend to grow because of rent seeking, pork-barrel politics, deficit
spending, and a tax system with loopholes, exemptions, credits, and so
on. A massive expansion of the power to tax has enabled public
officials to promote evermore alleged social ends.
The rules of decision making regarding public spending are outlined in
the constitution and create in the representatives a tendency to spend
more than the revenue collected. Democratic governments have a
significant tendency toward deficit spending unless they are
constrained by some fundamental constitutional principle like that of
the classical balanced budget. In addition, there was once the
pre-Keynesian principle that public expenditures were to be funded by
taxation and private spending was to be financed with people's income.
Both citizens and politicians abandon their fiscal discipline when
they resort to a debt-financed government. When the proper scope of
the government is extended, it is difficult to limit its expansion.
When budgets are maximized and deficits are incurred, the results
include higher government spending, inefficient allocation among
government agencies, and inefficient production within them.
Keynesians have failed to consider the implications of the
intergenerational transfer of the debt burden. The burden of debt is
passed on to future generations rather than paid for currently with
the consumption of real resources. The phenomenon of stealing through
the majoritarian processes of government is exacerbated through fiscal
deficits that produce intertemporal wealth transfers.
Buchanan claims that we need fundamental
constitutional change if special interest legislation and factional
rent-seeking or transfer-seeking activity is to be minimized. He says
that we should be concerned with processes or procedures (i.e., rules
and principles) through which interacting individuals create certain
states of affairs. Men need to rethink and redesign their
institutional structures in order to revive the classical political
economy of the 18th century. He says that lasting reform results from
adopting a constitutional perspective with respect to systemic change
in the rules of government.
Buchanan employs primarily an "economic man" assumption and sees
government officials as revenue maximizing rather than as wealth
maximizing. He therefore wants rules that constrain the
revenue-raising ability of government and the government freedom to
select the spending mix. Buchanan advocates constitutional revisions
in order to provide safeguards and to avoid a slippery slope. He says
that taxes should be earmarked for particular services so that each
type of government activity is financed by a tax on a base that is
logically related to that activity. Buchanan explains that a system of
multiple excise taxes, rather than a small number of broad-based taxes
would enable taxpayers to better control government by allowing them
to avoid some taxation by decreasing their purchases of high-taxed
items. In addition, he advocates constitutional rules requiring
balanced budgets. Under a balanced budget requirement, money would be
so limited compared to demand for it that near unanimity would be
required before financing for a project would be approved.
Buchanan says that his contractarian approach and unanimity principle
provide a way of normatively evaluating existing constitutional
provisions and proposed constitutional changes. Unanimity thus becomes
the benchmark for efficiency. He predicts that something like a 2/3
super-majority rule for the operations of the productive state should
be, and would be, agreed upon at the constitutional stage. Buchanan
says that people would want rules that are not so permissive that they
permit the demise of individual property rights.
Contractual Rights versus Natural
Rights |
Buchanan states that each person has an ethical obligation to join an
ongoing constitutional dialogue but he fails to adequately describe
the source of this ethical obligation. Remember that he has dismissed
the possibility of any absolute moral values. He is a social
contractarian who does not subscribe to the notions of natural law,
natural rights, or natural objective moral value. Contractarian
individual rights for Buchanan come from having reached an agreement.
They are not something that is established by reference to human
nature. Buchanan's subjective, nominalist, and deterministic
philosophy would be much stronger if he had acknowledged that natural
rights are an objective characteristic of the human social realm. If
he had, then he may have realized that the "rules of the game" are
metanormative in nature and that only the protective state can be
justified. Such a state would be concerned solely with protecting the
self-directedness of individuals thus ensuring the freedom through
which individuals can pursue their flourishing and happiness. There
would be no justification for the productive state or the
redistributive state.
|