British defender of individual freedom and critic of state
coercion,
Herbert Spencer (1820-1903), believed that
inexorable human progress develops naturally when people are
free and their moral rights are protected. His law or
doctrine of equal freedom declares that a person's freedom
is restricted only by the equal freedom of others. When
equal freedom is the ultimate principle of justice
individuals are happier and more flourishing. Spencer states
that happiness can only be attained if a person is allowed
to express his right of freedom to do all that his faculties
induce him to do.
Spencer's case was
deterministic and based on Lamarckian evolutionary theory.
His notion of universal causation leads him to deny any
theory of free will. Spencer maintains that human nature
adapts over time to the conditions of social existence and
that acquired characteristics are imparted to later
generations. He explains that reason is an adaptive
mechanism and an apparatus to promote an individual's life-sustaining
actions. Spencer says that habitually-repeated live-affirming
actions lead to pleasure and become intuitive and that new
emotions adapt to new conditions.
Spencer explains that
social order does not require deliberate design and that
evolution leads to differentiation. Spencer thought that
individuation was a value generated by the evolutionary
process. He envisions change from a homogenous social
structure to a heterogeneous one with the highest stage of
community life being one of laissez-faire capitalism.
Distinguishing between a militant society, in which war
prevails and the government controls the lives of the
citizens, and industrial society where people produce and
trade peacefully, Spencer observes that the state interferes
with natural evolutionary processes. He anticipates the
development toward a society where conduct is regulated by
moral principles and competitive markets.
In ethics, Spencer argued
for a type of rational egoism. He explains that the
evolutionary process is progressive in a moral sense given
the appropriate conditions of a free society. Spencer
contends there is an innate and evolving moral sense through
which men access moral intuitions and from which moral
conduct can be derived. This moral sense represents the
accumulated efforts of inherited and instinctual experiences.
Carl Menger (1840-1921) developed a number of fundamental Austrian doctrines
including the causal-genetic approach, methodological
individualism, the connection between time and error, and
more. Menger incorporated purposeful action, uncertainty,
the occurrence of errors, the information acquisition
process, learning, and time into his economic analysis. He
was an immanent realist who considered a priori essences as
existing in reality. As an Aristotelian essentialist, he
wanted to investigate the essences of economic phenomena.
His goal was to discover invariant principles or laws
governing economic phenomena and to elaborate exact
universal laws. Menger acknowledged the co-existence of
different but complementary approaches to economics – the
realistic-empirical and the exact. To find strictly ordered
exact laws he said we had to omit principles of
individuation such as time and space. This entails isolation
of the economic aspect of phenomena and abstraction from
disturbing factors such as error, ignorance, and external
compulsion.
Menger taught that there
are objective laws of nature and that goods have objective
properties that make them capable of fulfilling men's needs.
He states that goods have no intrinsic or inherent value and
that value is a judgment made by economizing individuals
regarding the importance of particular goals for maintaining
their lives and well-being. People have needs as living,
conditional entities. The value of goods is contextual and
emerges from their relationship to our needs. Subjective
value (i.e., based on one's personal estimation) can be
viewed as individual, agent-relative, and objective.
According to Menger, judgments are subjective but the truth
or untruth of them can be determined objectively. The truth
requires correspondence of facts with the judgment that is
made. Menger thus contends that economic subjectivism is
compatible with philosophical realism.
Building upon the work of Menger,
Ludwig von Mises
(1881-1973) reconstructed economics upon the foundation of a
general theory of human action. His goal was to develop an
edifice of irrefutable, coherent, universally applicable,
formal economic theory using logical deduction and the sole
axiom of human action without employing any other empirical
or analytical assumptions. He says that it is possible to
deduce the entirety of the logic of economic behavior from
the fundamental undeniable axiom that men act. Mises
contends that the concept of human action is universal,
intuitive, a priori, and automatically built into each
person's mental structure. His action axiom is the
introspectively known fact that men act. As a neo-Kantian,
Mises sees the category of action as part of the human mind.
He contends that all of the categories, theories, or laws of
economics are implied by the action axiom.
Not only was Mises
dissatisfied with Menger's Aristotelian methodology, he was
also critical of Menger's value theory. He said Menger's
value theory was not consistent enough and that it retained
elements of the objective value theory of the classical
economists. Mises' sense of value is formal and indicates
nothing about whether an end is, in fact, valuable. He
speaks of nonnormative, personal, and subjective acts of
valuation. His subjective view of value takes human ends as
the ultimate given. All action is therefore viewed as
rational. For Mises, economics is a value-free science of
means rather than ends.
Mises' utilitarianism
proceeds from the method of axiomatic reasoning from true
premises – his utilitarianism is a priori. He deduces that
division of labor and social cooperation are more effective
and more efficient than social conflict as a means of
attaining one's self-interest. Social cooperation is
voluntary, contractual, maximizes individual free choice,
and results in greater prosperity in society. Mises views
social cooperation and coordination as a proxy for happiness
which is similar to the Aristotelian notion of human
flourishing. He says that although economics is value-free
and apolitical, it is still the foundation for a free polity.
Mises explains that value-free economics leads a person to
form a free society because the achievement of one's goal is
far more likely when people are left free than when they are
not. He maintains that it is by means of its subjectivity
that praxeological economics develops into objective
science. Mises, the praxeologist, takes individual values as
given and assumes that individuals have different
motivations and prefer different things.
The philosophy of
Ayn
Rand (1905-1982) is a systematic and integrated unity that
is founded on the axioms of existence, identity, and
consciousness. Rand explains that knowledge is based on the
observation of reality and that to attain knowledge a person
employs the processes of induction, deduction, and synthesis.
Her epistemology transcends both apriorism and empiricism.
She contends that it is possible to obtain objective
knowledge of both facts and values. Rand says that the
essential characteristics of a concept are epistemological (she
really means contextual and relational) rather than
metaphysical.
Rand maintains that
values are epistemologically objective when they are
discovered through objective conceptual processes and that
they are metaphysically objective when their achievement
requires conforming to reality. She argues that man's life
is the ultimate value and the standard of value for a human
being – a creature possessing volitional consciousness. Her
naturalistic value theory states that it is the concept of
life that makes the concept of value possible and that
reason is a man's only judge of value. Rand states that it
is possible for a person to pursue objective values that are
consonant with his own rational self-interest. According to
Rand, ethics is rational, objective, and personal. Her
rational egoism is based on the Aristotelian idea that the
objective and rational end of a human being is his
flourishing and happiness – egoism is a virtue because
nature requires it. A person has the natural right to
initiate his own conduct in line with his own judgment. She
views rights as the link between a person's moral code and
society's legal code.
Murray Rothbard
(1926-1995) did not accept Mises' neo-Kantianism, but still
argued that the action axiom is true – he says that a person
becomes aware of action through experience in this world.
Rothbard, working within an Aristotelian or Thomistic
tradition, maintains that the action axiom is a law of
reality that is empirical rather than a priori.
Rothbard contends that
economics as a science is value-free and that economics and
ethics are separate disciplines. He does go beyond economics
to formulate a metanormative objective ethics that affirms
the essential value of liberty. Rothbard explains that
liberty deals with matters of private property, consent, and
contract. He maintains that liberty supplies a universal
ethic for human conduct and provides a moral axiom – the
nonagression axiom which holds for all persons no matter
their location in time or space.
Rothbard derives a
radical dualistic separation between political ethics and
personal ethics. He distinguishes between the metanormative
sphere of politics and the normative domain concerned with
moral or ethical principles of one's flourishing – there is
a huge difference between having natural rights and the
morality or immorality of the exercise of those rights. He
considers nonaggression to be an absolute principle prior to
any foundation for personal morality. An individual's
personal moral values are separate from, but dependent upon,
the existence of a liberal social order. Being morally
neutral regarding various individuals' values and goals,
Rothbard ended his ethics at the metanormative level.
Considering the state to be a totally evil coercive
institution, he was an anarcho-capitalist who advocated
natural order with competing security, defense, conflict
resolution, and insurance suppliers.
Friedrich A. Hayek
(1899-1992) was concerned with the nature, scope, limits,
use, and abuse of reason and formulated a largely
antirationalist theory of a free society based on the
inevitable ignorance and fatal conceit of intellectuals who
think that they can design an economy better than what would
result from the voluntary interactions of individuals.
Developing an elaborate attack on constructivist rationalism,
Hayek explains how little men know about what they design.
He says that bureaucrats, whose fated conceit is their undue
faith in reason, have no way to make intelligent decisions
with respect to deliberately designing or planning an
economy. Hayek observes that centralized policy leads to the
suppression of creativity, growth, and progress. He argues
that relevant knowledge cannot be centralized in the hands
of a person or a group who make such policy. Seeing a very
limited role for reason, Hayek says that any person's
knowledge is limited, incomplete, and uncertain. He,
therefore, favors concrete practical knowledge and
institutions and social order that are the product of human
actions but not of human design.
Emphasizing the
importance of decentralized decision making, Hayek explains
that markets employ knowledge beyond what could be acquired
by a central authority. He says that knowledge is a product
of trial, error, and adaptation resulting in unplanned
evolutionary progress. For Hayek, all knowledge is
essentially tacit existing in the habits or dispositions of
people to act in a rule-governed manner. He views social
institutions and rules of conduct as vehicles of knowledge.
According to Hayek, moral
conventions are not objective, invariant, or immutable and
they are a part of the evolving and spontaneous social order.
He states that moral conventions frequently are unable to be
articulated. His evolutionary epistemology and ethics
emphasize the socially-constructed nature of man – norms are
ingrained in the biological and social structure of men and
their markets. Hayek contends that people develop ideas
passively and intuitively. Hayek does not defend free will –
he says that free will is a phantom problem. As a post-Kantian,
he believes that the categories of men's minds evolve. Hayek
has a mechanistic and evolutionary concept of science and
does not acknowledge natural laws or natural rights.
He does say that society
requires rules of conduct that are minimal and spontaneously
generated. Hayek distinguishes between two types of law –
general rules of justice (i.e., general principles of
conduct) and rules concerning the internal operations of
government. Despite this, he ultimately accepts some form of
welfare safety net. In the end, Hayek was not a consistent
thinker and he failed to complete a systematic political and
economic philosophy.
The neo-classical Chicago
School economist,
Milton Friedman (1912- ), did not provide
a philosophical case for a free society. Instead, he relied
on skepticism, ethical subjectivism, the notion of the
greatest happiness for the greatest number of people, and
the results of detailed empirical studies of government
intervention. Friedman explains the errors of statism,
skillfully refutes interventionist arguments, and applauds
the coordinating mechanism of the free market, but has
little to say about the nature of man or the ethical basis
of capitalism. His highest ethical principle is the absence
of coercion – he explained that political freedom could not
be attained without economic freedom including private
property. Friedman attempts to demonstrate the superiority
of a free society on purely empirical grounds.
Friedman's major
achievements occur in the fields of monetary history,
monetary theory, and consumption analysis. His economics is
actually somewhat Keynesian in that it is macro-economic and
demand-focused. Friedman's positive economics says that a
theory is useful if the theory allows individuals to predict
occurrences of some phenomenon. He desires accurate
predictions and simplified assumptions. Friedman rejected
introspection and the realism of assumptions. He even
applauds the virtues of descriptively false assumptions and
has said that wildly inaccurate representations of reality
in assumptions are acceptable if accurate predictions occur.
Friedman is a falsificationist who states that confirming a
proposition does not add to the probability that a theory is
true. For him, abstraction involves a theory in which many
actual characteristics are disregarded as absent in the
theory. Friedman views any theory as deficient and false
when it does not specify all of the characteristics of
reality including all irrelevant, non-explanatory, and
extraneous ones.
Public Choice economist,
James M. Buchanan (1919- ) has analyzed the nature, workings,
and failings of governmental, political and bureaucratic
processes. Expanding economic analysis to politics, he built
upon contractual and constitutional foundations in his
theory of political and economic decision making. Buchanan's
methodology includes rational choice, individual utility
maximization, contractarian rights, and politics as
exchange.
Buchanan employs
deductive logic and conjectural history to discover how a
constitutional order could have come about. He states that a
legitimate social structure must ultimately stem from
individual choice. His proceduralist contractarianism uses
the Hobbesian model when he deduces contractarian consent
for limited government as an alternative to anarchy and
lawlessness. Buchanan's social contractarian approach
repudiates the possibility of natural law, natural rights,
and objective moral values. Although Buchanan's hypothetical
state of nature is somewhat Hobbesian, he also believes that
man has Lockean characteristics – Buchanan is not as
pessimistic as Hobbes.
Buchanan's contract
theory of the state explains that people agree to a social
contract because of their desire to survive. He observes
that men make constitutional decisions under a veil of
ignorance or uncertainty and that under this veil unanimity
is both conceivable and likely. He argues strongly for the
principle of unanimity at the constitutional stage of
collective choice. Buchanan states that constitutional-level
law places restrictions on individual freedom that permits
people to progress. It follows that a coercive agency, the
state, originates by necessity to enforce the social
contract.
Buchanan discusses two
levels of public choice – the first or constitutional level
establishes the rules of the game and the second or post-constitutional
level deals with playing the game within the rules.
Constitutional politics sets boundaries for what ordinary
politics is allowed to do. According to Buchanan, ordinary
political decisions are often made by majority voting – the
unanimity principle is not feasible at this stage. Buchanan
wants a new constitution that requires much higher than
majority agreement at the post-constitutional level in order
to make it more difficult to fund government activities.
Harvard philosopher,
Robert Nozick (1938-2002), tried to justify the state and to
dismiss anarchy. Nozick begins by merely assuming the
existence of Lockean individual rights – he makes no attempt
to derive them from a philosophical examination of human
nature. He sees natural rights as limits to action or as
boundaries that circumscribe the "moral space" around an
individual. Unfortunately, his moral space doctrine and
Lockean natural rights are not underpinned by a convincing
moral theory. Nozick's sole reason for his theory of rights
is a deontological appeal based on intuition. As a Kantian
deontologist, he has also said that there exists no
unambiguous concept of human nature that always defends
individualism. As many have observed, there is an
incoherence, inconsistency, and incompleteness in Nozick's
body of thought.
Nozick says that in the
state of nature, a man may enforce his own rights by
defending himself. He contends that it is from this state of
nature that rational and rights-respecting behavior will
lead to a limited government form of political order. He
attempts to show how a state would arise from anarchy
through a process involving no morally impermissible
actions. Nozick explains the emergence of the state, as
dominant protection agency, through self-interested choices
of people in the state of nature. He says that a
monopolistic defense agency will arise and agree to supply
protection to all those who have contracted with smaller
protection agencies that it drives out of business. Many
critics have commented that, if force had been used to
establish the state's monopoly, then the state may have come
about immorally. Nozick's entitlement theory of justice
emphasizes just acquisition of property and is based on
Lockean ideas. He explains the role of the government is to
protect natural rights including property rights. Nozick
also defends the idea of process equality which means equal
treatment before the law.
Nozick wants people to be
free to voluntarily join together in the pursuit of a good
life. He has said that the minimal state should go no
further than enforcing the most basic level of ethics
required for peaceful cooperation – a state limited to
protection against force, fraud, and theft and concerned
with enforcing contracts is justified. According to Nozick,
only negative rights (i.e., the ethics of respect) should be
coercively enforced by the state. The ethics of respect
requires voluntary cooperation to mutual benefit and its
principles mandate the respect of another's life and
autonomy. He says that the ethics of respect is the
foundation that should be compulsory across all societies –
all other ethical levels are optional and concerns of
personal choice. Nozick emphasizes that there is a duty not
to interfere with another individual's domain of choice.
Thomas Sowell (1930- )
draws from Hobbes, Smith, Hayek and Friedman in developing
his constrained or tragic vision of man and society.
Accepting the realities of the human condition, Sowell sees
trade-offs but no solutions. He explains that a man's
personal knowledge is far less than organized systemic
knowledge and that markets economize on the knowledge needed
by any one individual – no one has to possess complete
information in order for the economy to convey relevant
information through prices. Championing the supremacy of
systemic rationality, Sowell states that knowledge consists
largely of the unarticulated experiences and rationality
embedded in traditions, customs, and systemic processes such
as markets, families, and languages. He maintains that
individuals lack the intellectual and moral ability for
deliberate comprehensive planning based on intentional
rationality. Sowell views freedom as a process
characteristic and rights as boundaries or rigidities that
limit the exercise of government power and establish areas
for individual discretion.
A leading Catholic social
theorist,
Michael Novak (1933- ), relies on he work of
Aristotle, Aquinas and the Scholastics, Tocqueville,
Maritain, Locke, Smith, and the Austrians to develop his
concept of democratic capitalism which consists of a market
economy, a limited democratic government, and a pluralistic
moral-cultural system. Novak particularly heralds the
Austrian School of Economics for its contributions to the
restoration of economics as a field worthy of study by moral
philosophers. He views personalism as described in Catholic
papal encyclicals especially Pope John Paul II's view of the
human person as subject, to be consonant with Austrian
economic theory. Novak is thus concerned with "the acting
person."
Novak explains that the
human person is free, self-responsible, and accountable
before God. He says that the right of personal economic
initiative fulfills the image of God inherent in every
person because each one of us is capable of insight and
love. Concerned with the moral virtue of creativity, Novak
maintains that people need a social system to enable them to
create wealth in a systematic and sustained manner.
Explaining that the human mind is the cause of wealth, he
describes human economic progress as the capacity to create
more in a lifetime than one consumes. Novak sees the free
market and private ownership leading to positive-sum
transactions in which each party benefits.
Skeptical of state power,
Novak sees the limited state and the rule of law as man-made
means of securing liberty and justice for all men. He
espouses the principle of subsidiary, freedom of
association, and the importance of mediating institutions.
Novak has done much to improve upon and update the teachings
of Aquinas and to bring the Catholic Church ever closer to
embracing capitalism.
This brief review has shown that throughout history thinkers
have held a range of perspectives with respect to the
theoretical defense of a free society. We can learn a great
deal from a survey of political and economic thinkers. We
can draw from and integrate the teachings of many of them in
our efforts to construct a conceptual foundation and edifice
for a free society.
My next essay will see
what we can use to elucidate a theory of the best possible
political regime on the basis of proper conception of the
nature of man, his actions, and society. Such a paradigm for
a free society will address a range of issues in metaphysics,
epistemology, value theory, economics, ethics, and so on in
a systematic fashion. We will find that many of the ideas
employed have had origins deep in the history of political
and economic thought. There are a number of contemporary
thinkers whose writings, I believe, agree with most of what
I will present in my next essay. Among the most prominent
are Tibor R. Machan, Douglas B. Rasmussen, and Douglas J.
Den Uyl.
|