The central human motive force – self-interest – can lead
either to a harmonious free-market society where a minimal
government rigorously protects property rights or to a
society where plunder is the norm and is enshrined in the
law. Both of these systems, in turn, direct the self-interest
motive further to either beneficial or harmful ends. This
paper shall next examine Bastiat's understanding of
self-interest's function within the systems of free
markets and of legal plunder.
Self Interest in a Free-Market
Society |
Bastiat devoted his 1845 work, Economic Harmonies, to
explaining how the market coordinates individual desires and
activities to lead to prosperity for all. He observed that a
city as populous as Paris can get enough food to sustain all
of its inhabitants without any central direction: "Remarkably,
that regularity is not designed or maintained by any grand
master. It results from the acts of countless individuals
looking after their own interests." (Richman, p. 10)
Paris can get fed, and all other social needs provided,
without government involvement. To convey this idea, Bastiat
first needed to expose the conflation – common from ancient
times to the present day – between society and government.
Instead of the two being equivalent, society is "the
spontaneous ordering of people interacting and voluntarily
exchanging their goods" (Barry, p. 21). Thus, just
because a given service, practice, or commodity is necessary
for the survival of a society does not imply that government
needs to provide it. Self-interested individuals recognize
the importance of the good in question and voluntarily
arrange for its provision. Provided that these arrangements
are entirely consensual, they are always more effective than
government provision: Bastiat believed that "there is an
inevitable harmony in the world if only politicians
would get out of the way and allow free individuals to
coordinate their activities subject to a minimum of rules (derived
from natural law)" (Barry, p. 19).
The power of self-interest as a human motive explains why
private economic action is more effective than government
action. Self-interested individuals are faced with a world
where actions not only have direct and immediately visible
primary consequences, but also indirect secondary effects
removed in time:
In the economic sphere an act, a habit, an
institution, a law produces not only one effect, but
a series of effects. Of these effects, the first
alone is immediate; it appears simultaneously with
its cause; it is seen. The other effects
emerge only subsequently; they are not seen;
we are fortunate if we foresee them. |
To be effective in their actions, individuals must learn to
recognize secondary effects. "Two very different masters
teach" man to take secondary consequences into account: "experience
and foresight. Experience teaches efficaciously but brutally.
It instructs us all in the effects of an act by making us
feel them." Once individuals have had
disappointing experiences due to their failure to take
secondary consequences into account, they will change their
actions to adjust for what they have learned – because they
wish to fulfill their self-interested desires effectively.
To ease the pains of the learning process, Bastiat advises
economic actors "to replace this rude teacher with one more
gentle: foresight." As a teacher of
economic principles, Bastiat himself hoped to increase the
foresight with which individuals acted to fulfill their
aspirations.
In a free-market system, however, foresight is a natural
tendency for individuals – who are free to change their
actions on the basis of their improved information about the
world. Because each individual is responsible for his own
actions on the free market, his success will depend directly
on the efficacy with which he foresees secondary
consequences: "[u]nder such an administration, everyone
would understand that he possessed all the privileges as
well as all the responsibilities of his existence." An individual thus free and responsible knows that he
has only himself to praise for his successes or to blame for
his failures: "No one would have any argument with
government, provided that his person was respected, his
labor was free, and the fruits of his labor were protected
against all unjust attack." The government
would not be accused of bearing responsibility for
individual misfortunes, any more "than would the farmers
blame the state because of hail or frost." Thus, Bastiat thinks that a free-market society would also
have a stable and well-respected government to which people
would be grateful for its services in protecting against
plunder. No considerations besides the effectiveness with
which the government protected individual rights would
affect the government's reputation or threaten it with
overthrow and revolution.
In a free-market system, self-interest would lead
individuals to prioritize their wants and objectives
in a logical manner. We would not see poor families
seeking literary instruction before they have bread.
We would not see cities populated at the expense of
rural districts, nor rural districts at the expense
of cities. We would not see the great displacements
of capital, labor, and population that are caused by
legislative decisions. |
Most individuals will, from experience and foresight, come
to understand what is necessary for their preservation and
which necessities, comforts, and opportunities of life
depend on which others. This prioritizing will lead to the
greatest possible prosperity, the most equally distributed
prosperity, and the greatest happiness – a claim Bastiat
supports with empirical evidence:
Which countries contain the most peaceful, the most
moral, and the happiest people? Those people are
found in the countries where the law least
interferes with private affairs; where government is
least felt; where the individual has the greatest
scope, and free opinion the greatest influence;
where administrative powers are fewest and simplest;
where taxes are lightest and most nearly equal, and
popular discontent the least excited and the least
justifiable; where individuals and groups most
actively assume their responsibilities, and,
consequently, where the morals of admittedly
imperfect human beings are constantly improving… |
In The Law, Bastiat considers England, Holland,
Switzerland, and the United States during his time to have
exhibited the above characteristics. He showed a link
between the freedom of the economy in a society and the
prevalence of virtue among its inhabitants. Left to their
own devices and freed from the threat of plunder by a just
government and system of laws, self-interested individuals
have every natural impulse to improve morally and to prosper.
Self-Interest in a Society of
Legalized Plunder |
In a society where plunder is enshrined in the law, however,
self-interest will motivate individuals to undertake actions
which exacerbate the occurrence of legal plunder. If
the law authorizes plunder, wrote Bastiat, the plundered
individuals will wish to enter the legislative arena and
change the law: "According to their degree of enlightenment,
these plundered classes may propose one of two entirely
different purposes when they attempt to attain political
power: Either they may wish to stop lawful plunder, or they
may wish to share in it." Bastiat offers a
society imperiled by plunder a way out of its predicament
through the economic and moral enlightenment of individuals.
Absent that enlightenment, however, it is far less costly
and more lucrative for these new entrants into law-making to
perpetuate the plunder and merely redirect it than it is for
them to abolish legalized plunder altogether. If the
suffrage is extended to the plundered classes, it will hence
result in more plunder, not less – a tendency Bastiat
observed in France, where the suffrage was extended to the
bourgeoisie after the July 1830 Revolution and to the
working classes after the 1848 Revolution while the scope of
government redistribution, coercion, and taxation only
ballooned. Bastiat explains that "[i]nstead of rooting out
the injustices found in society, [the formerly plundered
classes] make these injustices general. As soon as the
plundered classes gain political power, they establish a
system of reprisals against other classes. They do not
abolish legal plunder." Thus, legalized
plunder is self-reinforcing: it draws into government the
plundered classes, who further amplify the amount of
legalized plunder.
A government that legalizes plunder attracts a variety of
rent-seekers. Bastiat noted that "[b]ecause of its power to
tax and coerce, [the state] became the main agent of plunder,
and it naturally attracted people who wanted an extra-market
income" (Barry, p. 21). Once the government engages in
redistributive activities, the rent-seekers see an
opportunity and grasp it. The rent-seekers – including
associations and combinations of industries, workers, and
other special-interest constituencies – wish to direct the
law "to prevent rivals from competing, to restrict the
domestic and foreign trading opportunities of other
consumers in the society, and therefore to steal the wealth
of one's neighbors" (Ebeling, p. 30). The rent-seekers
advise government to engage in such regulation, and
government officials are all too eager to oblige. Roche
cites Bastiat on this tendency: "Alas! The state is only too
ready to follow such diabolical advice; for it is composed
of cabinet ministers, of bureaucrats, of men, in short, who,
like all men, carry in their hearts the desire, and always
enthusiastically seize the opportunity, to see their wealth
and influence grow" (Roche, p. 147). In a redistributive state, the government officials can increase
their own power over men by indulging the rent-seekers; they
will follow their self-interest to do so where the law
allows them.
Any time the law and the scope of government are extended
beyond the essential protective functions of the minimal
state to pursue the goal of "equalizing" the distribution of
property, rent-seeking will result, since "[t]he law can be
an instrument of equalization only as it takes from some
persons and gives to other persons. When the law does this,
it is an instrument of plunder." The law can
either protect the property rights of all, or it can deprive
some of property to fulfill the positive ambitions of others;
the second function necessarily undercuts the first. For
Bastiat, the test for seeing whether legal plunder occurs is
simple: "See if the law takes from some persons what belongs
to them, and gives it to other persons to whom it does not
belong. See if the law benefits one citizen at the expense
of another by doing what the citizen himself cannot do
without committing a crime."
The consequences of legalized plunder for social and
political stability are devastating: "The sources of our
existence are made uncertain and precarious by these state-created
displacements. And, furthermore, these acts burden the
government with increased responsibilities."
If government involves itself with ever more areas of human
existence, it will also be ever more vulnerable in the event
that misfortunes, errors, and failures occur in those areas.
A minimal state would not be faulted for mistakes in the
production of grain, poor quality of education, or sub-optimal
workplace safety standards – because it would be clearly
recognized that the state's function does not extend to
these spheres. On the other hand, an interventionist,
redistributive state would involve itself in these areas and
incur the blame if it does a poor job – greatly increasing
the likelihood of social unrest, upheaval, and even
revolution. Bastiat recognized that if "the law is
responsible for all individual misfortunes and all social
inequalities – then the door is open to an endless
succession of complaints, irritations, troubles, and
revolutions."
Bastiat also recognized that a society of legalized plunder
will direct individual self-interest toward immorality. In
the first place, a government-planned society eliminates the
need for individual foresight and initiative:
It substitutes the will of the legislator for [individuals']
own wills; the initiative of the legislator for
their own initiatives. When this happens, the people
no longer need to discuss, to compare, to plan ahead;
the law does all this for them. Intelligence becomes
a useless prop for the people; they cease to be men;
they lose their personality, their liberty, their
property. |
If individuals are no longer free to act upon what
experience and foresight teach them, then experience and
foresight cease to have a direct link to individual economic
success or failure. The criteria that government regulators
use to determine who gets taken care of and who does not are
not the natural criteria of the free marketplace, but rather
artificial criteria which have little to do with prudence or
virtue and which often conflict with them. Yet still, it is
in the self-interest of individuals to meet the government's
criteria so that they can get taken care of. In this way,
legalized plunder "erases from everyone's conscience the
distinction between justice and injustice," since people must now appeal to the apparatus of coercive
redistribution and rights-violation to acquire their
subsistence; it is not clear to them anymore what justice is
if they must resort to injustice to survive.
Furthermore, individuals' ethical expectations are adversely
affected by the redistributive state: "The basic immorality
involved in coercion of men soon corrupts not only the
wielder of such power, but those over whom the power is
wielded. Soon all men come to expect that their lives should
be rendered problem-free by an omnicompetent state" (Roche, p. 150). Instead of striving to be autonomous,
creative, and active, individuals become passive and
dependent on government handouts. The person who retains a
sense of morality and of the wrong entailed in coercing and
expropriating human beings is put in a double-bind: he "has
the cruel alternative of either losing his moral sense or
losing his respect for the law." The law in a
redistributive state conflicts with morality and often is
used to punish the moral people who seek to protect
their own property: "It has converted plunder into a right,
in order to protect plunder. And it has converted lawful
defense into a crime, in order to punish lawful defense." Such a system gives self-interested
individuals the overwhelming incentive to abandon morality
and prudence and give in to the temptation to partake in the
plunder; in the long run, of course, this tendency will
devastate the society.
Bastiat's analysis of self-interest's economic role does not
classify self-interest as either wholly and universally
good or wholly and universally evil; self-interest,
motivated by different incentives and constrained by
different circumstances, will produce vastly different
results. Bastiat is not a naïve optimist about the ability
to isolate the beneficial consequences of self-interest from
the harmful ones: while it would seem that a law strictly
confined to the protection of property will fulfill this
task, attaining such a law is immensely difficult. The very
adverse facets of self-interest against which just laws must
protect motivate the lawmakers to pervert the law and
legalize plunder. Not only is this phenomenon possible, but
it has been more prevalent than not throughout the history
of human societies and governments – as Bastiat recognizes.
Bastiat does not despair, however, over the difficulty of
achieving liberty and justice – a task to which he devoted
his entire life. He hints at a way of doing so when he
states that the plundered individuals who are also
enlightened will seek to control the law not to perpetuate
the plunder, but to stop it. Thus, enlightenment
seems to be the means by which individuals might recognize
the harms which a redistributive state inflicts on
everybody and the inevitable failure of such "an attempt
to enrich everyone at the expense of everyone else."
Furthermore, Bastiat's wish that foresight rather than
experience were the primary guiding force of human learning
illustrates his understanding that foresight among most of
his contemporaries was insufficient to notice the ill
secondary effects of government redistribution,
protectionism, and regulation. This lack of foresight is
true of our time as well, as the scope of government and its
redistributive activities increase while far too few voices
point out the danger and inevitable harms of such trends.
Increasing individual foresight through the dissemination of
sound economic ideas, then, can be a powerful means of
combating legalized plunder and informing self-interested
individuals of the benefits of peaceful production and trade
over coercion and redistribution.
|