Compared to the glaring differences between a Nazi and an
advocate of the American constitutional order, the
distinction between a theist and an atheist is tiny. At
least political beliefs have a large relevance to the
organization of societies in this world; their consequences
have direct effects on human beings. Religious beliefs are
not even about this world – but another alleged one.
Other than by lengthy chains of reasoning – however often
performed by however many people – there is marginal, if any,
direct relevance of accepting or rejecting a god’s existence
to human action in this world. As Thomas Jefferson famously
stated, “it does me no injury for my neighbor to say there
are twenty gods or no God. It neither picks my pocket nor
breaks my leg.” Elaborate ideological systems, certainly,
have developed and asserted a connection between accepting
God’s existence and this or that course of conduct in the
human realm. But the conduct – insofar as it is actually
affected in this manner – follows not from the
acceptance of God per se, but rather from the acceptance and
individual interpretation of the ideological system
that claims to link God’s existence and the conduct. Nor
does the influence of the system on the conduct preclude the
possibility of altogether different systems arriving at the
same conduct. The assertions of Christians that Christianity
has made them more moral can seldom be disputed; many
individual Christians can offer ample and firm evidence for
ways in which their religion has enhanced their virtue. But
it does not follow from this that their route to
morality is the only route to morality and that no
other system of ideas – religious or secular – can serve a
similar function for someone else. What determines a
person’s morality or immorality is how he acts, not what he
believes. It is both conceivable and empirically true that
people can engage in the same actions while justifying those
actions by radically different systems of beliefs.
What, then, is right
conduct or morality? I contend that there exists conduct
which universally – across cultures, ages, degrees of
education, occupations, and ideologies – distinguishes a
moral individual from an immoral one. Morality does not
inextricably depend on a person’s thought, and it is
possible for a person to be moral without ever thinking
about issues of morality – for morality is expressed through
conduct alone. This conduct can be summarized, roughly but
comprehensively, by the exhortation, “Live and let live,”
with the caveat, “unless the other person does not let you
live.”
More specifically, what
does morality consist of? The first and most fundamental
moral conduct is negative; it consists not of doing, but of
not doing certain things. A person cannot be moral if he
violates the rights of innocent others to life, liberty, and
property – especially if he does so in an arbitrary manner.
This means that killing, injuring, confining, or
expropriating those who have not done likewise to others –
except as unintended collateral damage in times of war – is
the ultimate category of immorality. The abstinence from
coercion can be arrived at from a variety of intellectual
perspectives – among them the natural law tradition,
Christianity, utilitarianism, Objectivism, subjectivism, and
libertarianism. Each of them has their own justification for
this commitment, but the commitment itself is far more
important than the justification or even lack thereof. It
does not matter, by the way, whether the person who abstains
from coercion does so because he explicitly respects the
rights of others or simply out of convenience. If he figures
out that killing and robbing others is a poor idea because
no respectable person will sell him groceries afterward, he
is no less moral than the man who does not coerce because
his ideas forbid it. Nor does it matter if a person believes
in hypothetical instances where it would be justified
to coerce. Until and unless he enters such situations and
acts on his professed belief, he has not committed wrong
conduct and cannot be faulted for it. His only fault is with
his thought – and that is a mere error, not a question of
good or evil. To take this recognition to the extreme, even
an absolutely lazy person who does not kill simply because
it would be too much work or because the thought never
crosses his mind because he does not think much cannot be
held morally liable on this point of conduct. However, those
who violate this fundamental level of right conduct – for
whatever reason and with whatever motives or level of
awareness – can not only be morally condemned, but also
legally punished.
Second tier of moral conduct |
We move on to the second
tier of moral conduct: abstaining from any action or
inaction that would damage one’s own life. Again,
whether one’s body is a temple to God or an intrinsic value
in itself is less important than how one actually treats
one’s material organism. Furthermore, while the
justification for self-preservation is of secondary
importance, the intent of actions taken in that
direction has substantial relevance. The material aspects of
existence are often elusive and difficult for human beings
to control – and perfection in this control is not to be
expected, though overall historical improvement is. At times
people fail to maintain their health even with the best of
intentions – through no fault of their own. Their scientific
or practical knowledge may be insufficient; they might have
an improper view of material causality; they might fall prey
to illness or have genetic susceptibility to poor health.
None of this has a bearing on their moral standing –
provided they make their best efforts with what
understanding they have and what circumstances they live
under. The more significant part of the second tier of
morality is also negative: it requires individuals to
abstain from any conduct whereby they deliberately and
knowingly harm themselves and either outright damage or
needlessly endanger their own lives. Suicide is the primary
immoral conduct of the second tier; any other deliberately
damaging activity is immoral to the degree that it
approaches suicide in its effects. Again, intent matters
here. Most people who smoke cigarettes, for instance, do not
do so out of a desire to damage their lives. They simply
wish to experience the sensation which comes from smoking –
which they consider pleasurable. They do not wish to
damage their health, and if they could smoke without doing
so, they gladly would. Some might call their choice
imprudent, but it is not immoral. On the other hand, people
who consume “hard drugs” with the express purpose of
“getting wasted” are engaged in knowing and deliberate
self-destruction. Their alleged pleasure – though I see
nothing pleasurable about it – amounts to a reveling in
their organism’s steady disintegration; it is inseparable
from the damage the activity inflicts. The empirical
evidence coheres with this distinction: one can meet many
cigarette smokers who are evidently good people, whereas one
meets virtually no hard drug addicts who can be called moral
while not trying to battle their habit.
Engaging in immoral
conduct of the second tier is within an individual’s rights
and should not carry legal penalties – however morally
repugnant the conduct might be – provided that no others are
harmed against their wishes. However, it is perfectly
justified to socially ostracize individuals who engage in
such conduct or at least to attempt to persuade them to
alter their courses of action. There is no obligation to do
so, but nor is there any breach of propriety. Thus, we have
added the suicides and the hard drug addicts to the
murderers and thieves in our survey of immoral individuals.
This is not a problem for most people.
In an advanced society,
most moral issues arise on the third tier, the level of
civility and integrity. Civility is the respect
which one affords to other people on the basis of their
conduct alone and irrespective of any errors in their
thought. A civil person may well pass vocal judgment on
morally reprehensible actions – such as coercion,
suicide, rudeness, or dishonesty. He can also point out
calmly and respectfully if he disagrees with another
person’s ideas – but without denigrating either the person
or the ideas. He can state that he considers the ideas to be
vulnerable to this or that intellectual problem or this or
that practical consequence. A civil person does not
refer to ideas as “stupid” or “evil,” nor does he judge
individuals in that way solely on the basis of their
thoughts and without reference to their conduct. A person
who engages in warrantless demonizing and name-calling is
not a representative of civilization, but rather of the
fanaticism and intolerance which have at all times
threatened to return us to the savage world of intertribal
slaughter.
Integrity is the degree
to which an individual accurately esteems himself and
represents himself before others. A person of integrity does
not engage in self-deception, nor does he deliberately
attempt to deceive others – except where such deception can
effectively prevent immoral conduct of the first or second
tier. Telling a lie in order to preserve a person’s life or
property – or to prevent another’s self-destructive activity
– can be quite moral and indeed the best possible course of
action. Telling a lie to save a false reputation or gain an
unearned reward, however, constitutes clear immoral conduct.
A person of integrity honors all of his contracts and
promises – even when this is inconvenient and leads him to
forsake newly perceived advantages. He has a wide variety of
lifestyles, occupations, and habits to which he is free to
commit or not – but once he has made a commitment, he will
carry it out as he has resolved. He will give his word only
when he can assure for it the reliability of a natural law.
Civility and integrity
are the matters of conduct in which the vast majority of
immoral people are deficient. Civilizations can and do fall
if they are overcome by gangs of murderous savages – in
whatever guise – or by their own constituents’ wanton orgies
of self-destruction. But these extreme forms of peril are
often merely the culmination of a far longer and more
insidious process of moral decay on the third tier. Before a
society turns suicidal or murderous, the vast majority of
its members need to become uncivil to one another and
rampantly dishonest. Civil, honest people kill neither
themselves nor innocent others. The first two tiers are more
important than the third, but adhering to the third is a
virtual preventative against violating the first two.
If civil people fight
wars, they do so “without hate,” like Rommel, and they fight
over geopolitical objectives – not ideology. Soldiers on
both sides might die in the wars; there might be some
unintended collateral damage; but there is no genocide,
marauding, or deliberate targeting of non-combatants. The
worst kinds of wars are ideological – religiously, secularly,
or nationalistically so – because they are wars of entire
peoples, not mere wars of governments and troops. The
worst kinds of persecutions are ideological – religiously,
secularly, or nationalistically so – because they are
persecutions against entire peoples, not mere attempts by an
unstable ruler to neutralize a few potential rivals here and
there. Conflicts over ideology are always far more
devastating than conflicts over power, money, or resources.
A settlement – just or not – can always be arrived at over
the latter in order to prevent the worst atrocities.
Ideological conflicts are not subject to compromise; each
ideological fighter either seeks to fully convert the other
or destroy him.
The only way an
ideological conflict can ever begin is if somebody holds the
mindset, “My beliefs are the only right beliefs, and all
other beliefs are vicious and immoral.” From calling one’s
beliefs the only moral beliefs to persecuting those who hold
otherwise is a small intellectual step – and if the social
circumstances are conducive, many will take that step.
Intellectual intolerance can only exist alongside non-coercion
in an extremely materially prosperous society, and even then
not for long. Our society today is beginning to show signs
of a moral disintegration resulting from about four decades
of intellectual intolerance. From angry riots and campus
censorship to wanton murder in the streets is just a small
intellectual step. When the circumstances are conducive to
it – as in New Orleans after Hurricane Katrina – many will
take that step.
This is why it is
absolutely imperative today for all people who wish to be
called civil, decent, and moral to recognize that calling
one’s own ideology the only one compatible with moral
conduct goes against the preservation of civilization itself.
Sincerely claiming that only a belief in God can lead to
morality, or that only atheism can lead to morality, is
equally destructive of the third tier of virtue and renders
the first two open to future violation. Only when all people
judge one another on their actions alone and not on their
thoughts will civilization be secure. The number and variety
of ideas and ideologies will skyrocket as societies will
become increasingly heterogeneous in virtually every respect
except one. No matter how many directions civilized people
take in their thinking, they will all converge on the basic
principles of right conduct. But if people are restricted to
only following one direction – whatever that direction might
be – it will inevitably lead them astray.
|