Following a discussion of what morality
is, an
important practical question arises: how can we bring about more
morality and less immorality on all three tiers? To act morally or
immorally is ultimately an individual choice, and no number of
external factors, however powerful, can completely determine that
choice. Even a Nazi concentration camp guard raised solely on anti-Semitic
ideology had the choice to disobey his orders to torture and kill
innocent human beings; hence, he is rightly held morally responsible
if he acted on those orders. However, a number of external factors
can increase or decrease an individual's incentives to choose a
moral life over an immoral one. Ceteris paribus, an individual will
purchase more of a good at a lower price than at a higher price.
Similarly, ceteris paribus, an individual will tend to act more
morally in the face of greater incentives to do so than he would in
the face of lesser ones. Except for protecting individual rights
against the initiation of force, it is not the direct function of
government to bring about increased morality. Where, then, does one
start putting such incentives in place?
Every reader of this article is an individual who, in his personal
conduct, can choose to be moral or immoral. The best place to start
in advancing moral conduct is with oneself. As such, it is essential
to analyze the variety of personal incentives in place for moral
behavior on all three tiers.
Personal Incentives on the First Tier of Morality |
Irrespective of the legal structure of any given society, there are
in that society people who would not murder, rape, steal, defraud,
or otherwise violate the rights of their fellow men. In the face of
rampant chaos, with thugs running amok on the streets, these people
would still not resort to crime and would use violence only against
criminals. Such individuals do not even think about violating the
first tier of morality, and their default mode of operation in all
legal climates is the full respect of all men's natural rights. A
just system of laws and a firm code of criminal punishments deter
many from aggressing against others, but these individuals require
no such deterrence. They abstain of their own free will from what
the law seeks to forbid. What incentives influence them to so
unconditionally observe the first tier of morality?
Incentive 1.1. Personal Reverence for Life. No man would dare
aggress against what he deems sacred. Any deep-seated, sincerely
held conviction of the sanctity of every individual's life and,
correspondingly, his liberty, health, and possessions will serve as
the firmest deterrent against aggression for any given individual.
For the conviction to be efficacious, it does not matter how it is
arrived at whether it be through a reliance on God, reason, natural
law, utilitarianism, and/or a profound emotional pleasure in
observing human life flourish and develop. All that matters is that
the individual perceives the reasons for the conviction to be
unshakeable or that, if he should abandon one set of reasons
justifying non-aggression, he will replace it with another set of
reasons arriving at the same conclusion.
What are ways to cultivate such a reverence for life? Approaches to
reach this end can be abstract or concrete. A person can attain a
conviction of the sanctity of human life through reading didactic
literature or philosophy. The kinds of literature and philosophy
that will accomplish this vary in their basic premises; their
effectiveness depends primarily on the strength of the connection
they establish between their premises and the conclusion that
innocent human life must be respected. The more explicitly and
convincingly this conclusion is established in the literature, the
more likely the readers are to be inspired by it to act morally.
A concrete way to cultivate reverence for life is to extensively
observe or interact with living things. People who enjoy spending
time around children and domestic animals will find this concrete
cultivation of reverence to be easier. They will be able to observe
closely how these creatures behave and the immense beauty and
complexity of their approaches to the world. From loving and
appreciating children and animals to developing an unshakeable
respect for the innocent adult humans into which most children
develop is a small and fairly easy step both intellectually and
emotionally. While animals do not, strictly speaking, have rights,
and children do not have some of the lesser rights of adults (though
a child's right to life is as firm as that of any adult), both
animals and children let an individual thoroughly appreciate the
beauty of life and therefore render him less likely to commit acts
of aggression.
Incentive 1.2. Personal Productivity. Another concrete means of
arriving at unconditional respect for innocent human life is
pursuing occupations that cultivate and improve one's own life and
the lives of others. A person who enjoys building, developing ideas,
educating, raising children, or practicing medicine among numerous
other activities knows how much colossal effort is needed to engage
in life-sustaining activities. The mere thought of an aggressor
nullifying the effects of this effort through several seconds of
destructive activity will horrify the productive person. Certainly,
he will not want to personally engage in actions that will undo the
creative efforts of people like himself. Since the pursuit and
possession of property is integral to maintaining and improving
human lives, the productive person will tend to respect the hard-earned
property of others by seeing it as serving a vital role similar to
the functions of his own property.
Furthermore, every second spent in productive activity is a second
that cannot be spent in destructive activity. The more productive an
individual is in his life, the fewer opportunities he has to inflict
harm upon himself or others. As he continues to engage in productive
activities, he develops the skills suited to performing those
activities better while he does not develop the skills necessary for
aggression and destruction. Hence, not only will there be a time
constraint on his ability to aggress, but there will also be a skill
constraint. Since individuals tend to gravitate toward activities
where they are more skilled, a consistently productive individual
will tend to want to pursue productive activities rather than
destructive ones in direct correlation with his productivity.
Incentive 1.3. Personal Education. For most people, developing
productive hobbies, interests, and job skills is the best way to
become and/or stay moral. Mathematical faculties and morality of
conduct are distinct aspects of an individual, and a more
mathematically adept person is not necessarily more moral. However,
I am virtually certain that, if every individual in a society were
somewhat well-versed in the higher branches of mathematics, there
would be far less immoral conduct in that society than otherwise.
The reason for this is simple: most people in such a society would
be far more interested in finding the integral of x2e-x than in
engaging in street brawls or ingesting mind-altering drugs. They
will be more interested in pursuing the harmless activity they know
mathematics rather
than the harmful activities in which they are largely ignorant. An
education in other intricate disciplines whether they be productive
or merely non-destructive will tend to diminish a person's impulses
toward immorality, unless the education itself contains incentives
for immoral behavior. It is primarily by giving people extensive
skills in non-vicious activities that a quality education tends to
foster virtue.
Incentive 1.4. Harmless Entertainment. Activities that are neither
moral nor productive in themselves but are also neither immoral nor
destructive will tend to influence the individual pursuing them to
abstain from immoral activities. Let us presume that the board game
or computer game X is such an activity. The individual who plays X
does so not because he wishes to accomplish something or to live
morally, but simply because he finds X to be entertaining. Playing X
not only takes away time that could have been spent in immoral
activity, but also further cultivates the individual's skill at and
interest in X while not increasing his skill and interest in harmful
and destructive activities. While, from the viewpoint of
accomplishment, X is not as good a way to spend one's time as a
productive activity, it, too, can ward off desires to act immorally.
It can also offer an individual an opportunity to rest and
rejuvenate his energies after exerting himself in productive
activity while not at all endangering his morality.
Harmless pleasures of this sort include many board games, most
computer games, and some movies, radio shows, and television
programs. Many of these even carry peripheral benefits, though these
benefits are not the primary reasons that the activities are engaged
in. The general rule with regard to entertainment is: so long as it
does not advocate or insinuate immoral courses of action,
entertainment tends to be conducive to the moral conduct of
individuals consuming it. This can be seen by considering alternate
uses of individuals' leisure time had such harmless entertainment
not been available. Some people the ones already exceptionally
productive and motivated might have chosen to accomplish something
else instead, but these people are always and everywhere a minority.
Most would have pursued dissipative and destructive "pleasures" if
the harmless ones were not available. Furthermore, the violent
emotions of many would have found no outlet except in aggression
against other human beings. Today, an individual can choose to take
out his anger on fictitious monsters in computer games instead of
engaging in bar brawls or taking to the streets in riotous protest.
As the variety of harmless entertainment continues to increase, we
can expect to see a decrease in violent crime, all other things
equal.
Incentive 1.5. Personal Material Well-Being. Just as the presence of
harmless entertainment disinclines individuals from committing
immoral acts due to boredom or anger, so does the possession of a
sufficiently high material standard of living virtually eliminate a
person's motivation to violate the rights of others due to his wish
to satisfy his material desires. Rich men do not engage in theft in
order to survive, unless they earned their fortunes as thieves and
unless theft is their sole available means of earning further income.
Ceteris paribus, the more property an individual owns and the higher
an income he commands, the less inclined he will be to expropriate
others with the aim of materially enriching himself. Wealth alone
does not eliminate other motivations for crime, though it can
certainly help when combined with productivity, quality
entertainment, and a profound intellectual and emotional commitment
to morality. What is indisputably true, though, is that virtually
nobody in the Western world today will follow the example of Jean
Valjean from Les Misιrables and steal a loaf of bread to feed his
starving family for even those considered poor in the West today
have substantial access to food, clothing, and even cars and
televisions.
Personal Incentives on the Second Tier of Morality |
Reverence for life, productivity, education, harmless entertainment,
and material well-being all contribute to a person's great
reluctance to harm himself just as well as they deter him from
aggressing against others. Let us briefly consider how these
incentives manifest themselves in inspiring an individual to adhere
to the second tier of morality. The mention of each incentive is
accompanied by what a hypothetical moral individual might think
regarding it.
Incentive 2.1. Personal Reverence for Life. "I view innocent human
life as sacred, including my own. Therefore, my harming or
needlessly endangering my own life is out of the question."
Incentive 2.2. Personal Productivity. "If I harm my own life, I will
be unable to engage in the productive activities I enjoy. I will be
neither as accomplished nor as happy as I could have been."
Incentive 2.3. Personal Education. "If I harm my own life, I will
not be able to learn more about or practice the disciplines in which
I am well-educated. I will have wasted great knowledge and amazing
potential."
Incentive 2.4. Harmless Entertainment. "If I harm my own life, my
death, pain, or discomfort will prevent me from truly enjoying the
things I find pleasurable and entertaining.'
Incentive 2.5. Personal
Material Well-Being. "If I harm my own life, I will be unable to
enjoy the plenty of material things in my life which would otherwise
give me great comfort and convenience."
Other incentives assist in self-preservation as well.
Incentive 2.6. Pride in Oneself. Much vilified throughout history,
pride in oneself is no vice; in fact, it can be the source of great
personal virtue. Pride is here defined as a conviction of one's own
worth as a human being. A proud person considers himself to be
largely good, decently knowledgeable, adequately skilled, and
unapologetically important as a sovereign individual whose life is
worthy of living. This does not mean that a proud person views
himself as omniscient, infallible, or incapable of improvement.
Quite the contrary, his conviction in his own worth impels him to
constantly seek ways in which he might improve himself in every area
of his life. Furthermore, he always seeks a realistic estimate of
his own knowledge and abilities for such an estimate helps him make
the best use of his potential. With the help of a realistic
perception of himself, he will pursue tasks which he is genuinely
able to accomplish, thereby reinforcing his self-image and the good
reputation he seeks to have. He will avoid undertakings truly beyond
his ability for the inevitable failure in those will shame him
before himself and others, and the proud man will go out of his way
to avoid being shamed. Hence, the proud man never makes empty boasts;
if he says he will do something, it is because he knows he can.
The proud man using his meticulous capacity for self-evaluation will
constantly be on the lookout for ways in which he might be harming
himself and will systematically eliminate those tendencies once he
spots them. His pride leads him to seek his own advancement through
productive achievement; the more he accomplishes, the more he can
esteem himself. His high opinion of himself is also a powerful
stimulus to moral conduct, because one cannot consistently behave
like a brute or a criminal and yet still consider oneself good,
noble, or worthy. The proud man's reasoning is, "A man of my caliber
will not sink to the level of base or immoral conduct." The proud
man will seek to act so as to be worthy of his self-esteem. Since he
perceives himself as fundamentally good and his life as worth
living, he will have no reason to harm himself and every reason to
avoid such harm.
Incentive 2.7. Devotion to a Person, Thing, or Institution. Many
people are greatly disinclined to harm themselves because they are
strongly devoted to the well-being of some other individual,
possession, or organization. Beneficiaries of this kind of
commitment can be family members, friends, pets, treasured property,
or organizations. A person will be far less inclined to damage
himself if he understands that such actions will also harm his wife
and children, would cause his carefully cultivated estate to fall
into disrepair, or would bring about the ruin of his business. If a
person has worked immensely hard to achieve the well-being of his
family or of an organization he works for, he will be extremely
reluctant to endanger by wanton self-destruction what he has
hitherto strived to preserve and augment. Similarly, a man who sees
it as his purpose in life to promote a given idea will not wish to
hasten his own death for that would likely imply the peril of the
idea as well.
Incentive 2.8. Rejection of the Alternative. The alternative to life
and flourishing is death and suffering. Striving to avoid the latter
is as powerful a motivation for self-preservation as striving to
positively pursue the former. The thought of one's own non-existence
when seriously entertained is frightening, as well it
should be. Atheist-materialists have a powerful reason to preserve
their health and longevity in this world, because they believe that
there is no other world indeed, that their very individuality is
obliterated upon death. Believers in an afterlife will often still
feel extreme discomfort at the prospect of leaving a life of which
they are certain and with which they are familiar to possibly
journey to another world whose existence is not firmly established,
and whose aspects are unclear and disputed. Entertaining these
discomforts will in fact lead them to hold onto this life ever more
firmly and thus adhere to the second tier of morality. The fear of
death is a potent incentive to keep on living. It also helps the
religious if their God prohibits suicide and other desecrations of
his "temple" the human body. Those who adhere to such prohibitions
might even look forward to an afterlife, but they will not seek to
hasten its arrival, because they believe that doing so will deny
them the afterlife altogether.
Personal Incentives on the Third Tier of Morality |
We have hitherto explored powerful personal reasons to be moral in
not aggressing against others and in not wantonly damaging oneself.
For most people, at least one of these reasons is strongly
operational on each of the two tiers of morality. This is why, in
virtually every environment, the vast majority of individuals are
neither aggressors nor suicidal. Civility and integrity the virtues
of the third tier are much rarer, however. They require a special
set of incentives to augment those of non-aggression and self-preservation.
Incentive 3.1. Desire for a Good Reputation. A man with a good
reputation is well-thought-of by those with whom he comes into
contact. Those who seek a good reputation are most often moral, but
they also seek to be perceived as moral, because such a perception
on the part of others gives numerous advantages to oneself. People
who are considered moral are more often trusted in work and in
commerce, and are more frequently the beneficiaries of others'
generosity. Furthermore, they tend to find interactions with others
to be far more pleasant than those who are generally thought to be
morally questionable. Provided that a person genuinely practices the
virtues he espouses, there is no fault with seeking a good
reputation. In fact, a person who has a sound reputation will be
more reluctant to commit a moral infraction, because he fears the
accompanying loss of his good name. Moreover, if a person wishes to
be seen as moral without actually being moral, his hypocrisy will be
difficult to conceal and will require tremendous effort to keep
secret for any length of time. Once exposed, the hypocrite will be
despised to far greater extent than an honestly immoral individual hence,
the incentives against seeking a false good reputation are strong.
|