In a world where life is uncertain and often unpleasant,
there will tend to be an emphasis on some happier
supernatural future.
There may be nothing sinister in the loss of virtually the
whole body of Epicurean writings. Perhaps they were
destroyed by a triumphant Church that had room for Plato and
Aristotle but none for a naturalist enemy of all that
Christianity proclaimed. But there is no reason to suppose
any deliberate act of destruction. Papyrus rolls were by
their nature delicate things. They were also far more
expensive and therefore scarce in number than modern books.
In any European climate, a papyrus roll would last for about
a century, and then the glue that held it together would
perish. Without careful recopying, a work might easily be
lost.
The last centuries of the ancient world were mostly ages of
depression. There was a shortage of all the means that had
so far kept libraries together. Such means as remained were
naturally given to recopying works for which there was an
active demand. That means Christian theology, those parts of
the pagan philosophies that could be reconciled to
Christianity, and the greatest products of the pagan high
culture. Since, with the exception of Lucretius whose work
largely survived the works of Epicurus and his followers
were in a style remarkable only for its plainness, it is
unreasonable to suppose that librarians, forced to choose
what to copy and what to leave to die, would take up the 37
volumes of On Nature and not the Ecclesiastical History of
Eusebius.
So far as I can tell, whatever works of Epicurus survived
were not studied in the Byzantine Empire. In the West, all
but his name and whatever is said about him in Cicero
vanished for a thousand years.
And then something remarkable happened.
For the 19th century liberal and historian
of ideas William Lecky, the most striking fact about England
and France in the 17th century was the decline of belief in
the supernatural.(34) And the most striking instance of
this fact was the collapse of belief in witchcraft.
At the beginning of that century, belief in witchcraft had
been universal and unchallenged. James VI of Scotland
(1567-1625) was one of the most learned men of his day. He
believed without question in witches, and was a notable
persecutor. When he became King of England as well in 1603,
he brought his policies with him. It was to gain favour with
him that Shakespeare introduced the witchcraft theme into Macbeth.
James procured a law that punished witchcraft with death on
first conviction, even though no harm to others could be
proven. This law was carried in a Parliament where Francis
Bacon was a Member.
The law was given effect throughout England, and was
especially used during the interregnum years of the 1650s.
In 1664, under the restored Monarchy, Sir Matthew Hale one
of the greatest jurists and legal philosophers of the age,
presided over the trial of two alleged witches in Suffolk.
He told the jury that there could be no doubt in the reality
of witchcraft. He said:
For first, the Scriptures had affirmed so much; and secondly,
the wisdom of all nations had provided laws against such
persons, which is an argument for their confidence of such a
crime.(35) |
One of the witnesses called for the prosecution was Sir
Thomas Browne, one of the most eminent writers of the age.
Appearing as a medical expert, he assured the jury "that he
was clearly of opinion that the persons were bewitched."(36) They were convicted and hanged.
It was the same in France. In the town of St Claude, 600
persons were burnt in the early years of the century for
alleged witchcraft and lycanthropy. In 1643, Cardinal
Mazarin wrote to a bishop to congratulate him on his zeal
for hunting out witches.
Yet, in 1667, Colbert, the chief minister of Louis XIV,
directed all the magistrates in France to receive no more
accusations of witchcraft. Those convictions still obtained
he frequently commuted from death to banishment. By the end
of the century, witchcraft trials had all but ceased.
In England, belief collapsed later, but even faster than in
France. The last trial for witchcraft was in 1712. Jane
Wenham, an old woman, was accused of the usual offences. The
judge mocked the prosecution witnesses from the bench. When
the jury convicted her against his directions, he made sure
to obtain a royal pardon for the old woman and a pension.
Whatever the lowest reaches of the common people might still
believe, belief in witchcraft had become a joke among the
educated. And because of the tone they gave to the whole of
society, disbelief spread rapidly beyond the educated.
Anyone who tried to maintain its existence was simply
laughed at. Laws that had condemned tens or hundreds of
thousands to death, and usually to the most revolting
tortures before death, were now sneered into abeyance.
We should expect that a change of opinion so immense had
been accompanied by a long debate something similar to the
debates of the 19th century over Darwinism, or to the
debates of the day over the toleration of nonconformity. Yet
Lecky maintains that there was almost no debate worth
mentioning. There were sceptics, like Montaigne, who
disbelieved all accounts of the supernatural, or Hobbes, who
was a materialist and atheist. But, while, book after book
appeared in England during the late 17th century to defend
the existence of witches and the need for laws against them,
almost no one bothered to argue that witches did not exist.
Lecky says:
Several... divines came forward...; and they made witchcraft,
for a time, one of the chief subjects of controversy. On the
other side, the discussion was extremely languid. No writer,
comparable in ability to Glanvil, More, Cudworth, or even
Casaubon, appeared to challenge the belief; nor did any of
the writings on that side obtain any success at all equal to
that of [Glanvil].(37) |
Belief in witchcraft perished with hardly a direct blow
against it. What seems to have happened, Lecky argues, is a
change of world view in which belief in witches ceased to
have any explanatory value. We live in a world where,
orthodox religion aside, belief in the supernatural is
confined to the uneducated or the stupid or the insane. But
if we step outside the consensus in which we live, we should
see that there is nothing in itself irrational about belief
in the supernatural, nor even in witches. The belief is
perfectly rational granted certain assumptions.
Let us assume that the world is filled with invisible and
very powerful beings, that some of these are good and some
evil, that some human beings are capable of establishing
contact with these evil beings, and that some compact can be
made in which the power of the evil beings is transferred to
human control. Granting these assumptions, it becomes
reasonable to ascribe great or unusual events to magical
intervention, and to accept that it should be the purpose of
the law to check such intervention.
Now, the Platonic philosophies do accept the existence of
such beings. That is how Plato reconciled his One Creator
with the many gods of the Greek pantheon. This belief was
taken over by the Church Fathers, who simply announced that
the ancient gods were demons. It then continued into the
17th century. It seemed to explain the world. Doubtless,
cases came to light of false accusations and of people
convicted because they were ill rather than possessed by
demons. But our own awareness of corrupt policemen and false
convictions does not lead us to believe that there are no
murderers and that murder should not be punished. So it was
with witchcraft.
During the 17th century, however, the educated classes came
increasingly to believe that the world operated according to
known, impersonal laws, and that God assuming His
Existence seldom interfered with the working of these
secondary laws. In such a view of the world, the
supernatural had no place. Belief in witchcraft, therefore,
did not need opposition. It perished as collateral damage to
the system of which it was a part.
Lecky ascribes this intellectual change to
the growth of scepticism. This may have been part of the
answer. But while sceptics doubt the existence of the
supernatural, they do not necessarily affirm the existence
of invariable laws of nature. A more powerful cause of the
change may have been the revival of Epicureanism during the
first half of the 17th century.
In this revival, Pierre Gassendi (1592-1655) is the most
important philosopher. A French priest and professor of
philosophy, he conceived a strong dislike both of
Aristotelianism and of the new philosophy of Descartes. He
turned instead to Epicurus. His work falls into two parts.
First, there is the immense scholarship with which he went
through every extant ancient source to try to reconstruct
what Epicurus had said. Second, there is his attempted
reconciliation of Epicureanism and orthodox Christianity.
Briefly put, his reconciliation is to deny that the atoms
have existed from eternity and to deny that motion is
natural to them. The atoms were created by God, and they
move in paths directed by God. This being so, he cleared the
way for a view of the universe in which God exists, but
operates by secondary causes. For all practical purposes,
knowledge of the world is to be obtained by observing the
world.(38)
I say again that influences are very hard things to trace.
But there is no doubt that Gassendi had made all that
remained of the Epicurean writings available in one
convenient place, and had made some attempt to remove any
charge of impiety. These were important achievements. The
Dialogues of Cicero were part of the standard education; and
educated men would probably have read some Lucretius. But
hardly anyone had bothered to hunt out all the references
that set these into a greater whole. No one had yet
collected these in a single place. And no one had yet
laboured to overcome the religious prejudices that worked to
prevent an impartial reception of what had survived.
Nor is there any doubt that Epicureanism began suddenly to
exert a decisive influence over at least English science
from about the middle of the 17th century.
Edwin N. Hooker writes:
Scientists found [Epicurean physics] a highly useful working
hypothesis in their investigations in physical nature. But
by 1660 the working hypothesis had been blown up into a very
different shape, and in its altered shape was being peddled
as the final truth concerning nature, man, and human
society. The new monster had a wide appeal. In 1662 Edward
Stillingfleet wrote in Origines Sacrae that of all theories
the Epicurean at that time was making the greatest noise in
the world. A few years later John Wilkins, the remarkable
Bishop of Chester who had been for years the leading spirit
in that amazing group of scientists laboring at Oxford (a
group which became the nucleus of the Royal Society),
commented on the extravagant and irrational opinions then
afloat, inspired by Epicurus and his atoms. A little later
Ralph Cudworth, probably the most learned member of the
Cambridge Platonists, remarked that of late there had been
an extraordinary enthusiasm for Epicurus. From all sides
came testimony to the effect that Epicurus had indeed risen
from the dead and that the atomistic theory had burst its
seams.(39) |
What had risen from the dead may sometimes have been the
Epicureanism of the Master. But much was that of Gassendi.
Both Locke and Newton appear to have read Gassendi. There
are obvious similarities between them and this version of
Epicurus. Newton, for example, constructs his physics in
terms of matter and motion through a void. For him, light is
a stream of atoms. He accepts the revised physics of
Gassendi, denying any implicit motion to atoms, and then
goes further with his hypothesis of action at a distance, or
gravity.(40)
For the growth of empiricism and utilitarianism, it would be
necessary to write a book. These are both similar to the
ideas of Epicurus. They emerged in an intellectual climate
where Epicurus had been made available again and where he
had been made respectable to Christian orthodoxy. There is
no necessary reason to suppose that these facts are
connected. It may be that interest in Epicurus had revived
in a civilisation that was autonomously moving toward the
same general approach. But it does seem reasonable to
suppose a connection.
If, however, there was a connection, it was not merely a
revival of Epicurus and his philosophy. As in every other
recovery of ancient thought, save perhaps the cultural, the
moderns very quickly transcended the ancients. The moderns
began by revering the giants on whose backs they had climbed.
They soon grew into giants in their own right.
I have already mentioned the differences between Epicurus
and ourselves with regard to the natural sciences. Knowledge
for us is valued not mainly because it liberates us from
mental pain, but because it contributes to mental and
physical happiness. We observe. We form hypotheses. We
experiment. We make use of the mathematics that Epicurus
derided. We use the knowledge thereby gained to change our
conditions of life. We check suffering. We cure illness. We
extend life. We fill our lives with the wealth that comes
from our knowledge.
With regard to his ethical theories, the modern utilitarians
have also gone beyond Epicurus. They begin with the same
premise, that the purpose of life is happiness, but pass
then to the notion of the greatest happiness of the greatest
number. This leads them straight into the politics that
Epicurus rejected to an investigation of what social
orders are most productive of the general happiness, and to
a willingness to argue for the removal of impediments to
that happiness.
We can add to this the knowledge of economics that comes
from the application of Newtonian physics to human affairs
that is, the investigation of the natural forces that lead
spontaneously to the generation and maintenance of an order
in which individuals pursue their own happiness and promote
the happiness of others we come inevitably to the doctrine
of individual rights that is implicit in the philosophy of
Epicurus and that is central to modern classical liberalism.
The Debt We Owe to Epicurus |
Thomas Jefferson understood the value of
Epicurus. In 1819, he wrote to a friend:
As you say of yourself, I too am an Epicurean. I consider
the genuine (not the imputed) doctrines of Epicurus as
containing everything rational in moral philosophy which
Greece and Rome have left us... Their great crime [the
stoics] was in their calumnies of Epicurus and
misrepresentations of his doctrines; in which we lament to
see the candid character of Cicero engaging as an accomplice.
Diffuse, vapid, rhetorical, but enchanting. His prototype
Plato, eloquent as himself, dealing out mysticisms
incomprehensible to the human mind, has been deified by
certain sects usurping the name of Christians; because, in
his foggy conceptions, they found a basis of impenetrable
darkness whereon to rear fabrications as delirious, of their
own invention.(41)
So too did Ludwig von Mises. In Human Action, he says:
The historical role of the theory of the division of labor
as elaborated by British political economy from Hume to
Ricardo consisted in the complete demolition of all
metaphysical doctrines concerning the origin and the
operation of social cooperation. It consummated the
spiritual, moral and intellectual emancipation of mankind
inaugurated by the philosophy of Epicureanism.(42) |
When classical liberals and libertarians discuss the
intellectual roots of their ideas, they are quick to cite
Aristotle and Aquinas. It would show justice if Epicurus
could be given at least equal place of honour.
Indeed, whether or not you call yourself a libertarian, if
you are content to live in a world in which you can make the
best for yourself and your loved ones, in which there are no
supernatural terrors, but instead a body of natural science
that assists us in the pursuit of happiness, you too are an
Epicurean.
We have virtually everything that Plato wrote and almost
nothing that Epicurus wrote. But Plato has had no
discernable impact on the social sciences beyond providing
legitimation to various cliques of demented and often
murderous intellectuals. For all we have so few of his
writings, the ideas of Epicurus have survived. And they have
made the world a better place.(43)
|