|
Economic
Predictions, Central Planning and the Pretence of Knowledge (Print Version) |
by Jean-Hugho Lapointe*
Le Québécois Libre, April
15, 2011, No 288.
Link:
http://www.quebecoislibre.org/11/110415-13.html
An economist is an expert who will know tomorrow why the things he
predicted yesterday didn’t happen today. –Laurence J.
Peter
While most of us get the feeling that economic predictions are just as
unreliable as weather forecasts, demand for economic predictions somehow
remains very strong, as few people seem interested in their track
record. Indeed, the business of predicting the future is as old as
Antiquity, and has yet to significantly improve its flawed product, but
still, people keep flocking to the altar.
Nowadays, some segments of the prediction business, such as weather and
economic predictions, are cunningly marketed as "scientific forecasting,"
as they make extensive use of mathematical models. But since I am quite
certain that neither these models nor the predictions made using them
could ever be considered sufficiently reliable to be used as evidence in
a court of law to demonstrate knowledge of what the future holds, I have
always been puzzled by the fact that mainstream economists, who should
know better, use them to this very end. As a consequence of this, public
policy remains guided by economic forecasters and their models, despite
systematically humiliating results and terrible consequences for human
lives and society.
If astrologers and meteorologists have little influence on public policy,
economists predicting the future occupy strategic positions throughout
the public decision-making process, whether in government or at central
banks, nurturing the enactment of more and more wrongheaded large-scale
policies. That the work of economic forecasters continues to escape
close scrutiny seems disturbing at the very least, and prompted the
writing of this paper.
It’s the complexity, stupid!
Complex: involving a lot of different but connected parts in a way
that is difficult to understand. –Cambridge Learner’s Dictionary
As I pointed out, economic predictions are based on mathematical
economic models. In science, a model is generally understood as an
abstract representation of a given subject, such as a process or a
system. Mathematical models are models which use mathematical language
(data, equations) to describe their underlying systems, and are found in
a variety of fields such as physics, economics, biology, meteorology and
climatology, etc. Mathematical economic models are thus abstract
representations of an economy based on available data and equations. One
of the outputs of these models are quantitative predictions of the
future state of the economy depending on what actions are taken at a
given moment, allegedly similar to the way a model of the solar system
can predict the future position of the planets given the correct present
data.
Since mainstream economics relies on these tools to formulate theories
and prescriptions, mathematical economic models have become the
foundation of most advice guiding public policy, such as the setting of
interest rates, for some decades now. Indeed, once one assumes that we
can predict the state of the economy, what follows is the idea that we
can foresee the results of our actions, and therefore properly manage
society. Yet, as Albert Einstein said as far back as the early 40s:
When the number of factors coming into play
in a phenomenological complex is too large,
scientific method in most cases fails us. One
need only think of the weather, in which case
prediction even for a few days ahead is
impossible. Nevertheless no one doubts that we
are confronted with a causal connection whose
causal components are in the main known to us.
Occurrences in this domain are beyond the reach
of exact prediction because of the variety of
factors in operation, not because of any lack of
order in nature.(1)
Since that time, complexity theory has gained momentum in a variety
of scientific fields as a way of understanding complex systems, but it
seems that economic forecasting remains impervious. We will discuss
below what could become the next paradigm shift in economics.
Einstein was a dazzling thinker on a number of subjects, among them the
limits of science (or the philosophy of science). He was among the first
to identify the peculiar obstacles posed to science by complexity, and
on this he was followed by mathematician Warren Weaver, considered to be
a pioneer on the subject. Then, inspired by Weaver’s work, the first to
specifically discuss the scientific implications of complexity in
economics was Friedrich Hayek. In The Theory of Complex Phenomena
(1964), he pointed out that what distinguishes complex phenomena (such
as the economy) from simpler phenomena is the multiplicity of elements
and of their relationships within the system, coupled with the
subjectivity of the data in social sciences that eludes mathematical
formulae.
Nevertheless, complexity theory seemed to gain real traction only in the
90s, as described by Cornell mathematician Steven Strogatz:
Every decade or so, a grandiose theory comes along, bearing an
ominous-sounding C-name. In the 1960s it was cybernetics. In the
'70s it was catastrophe theory. Then came chaos theory in the '80s,
and complexity theory in the '90s. In each case, the skeptics at the
time grumbled that these theories were being oversold and that the
results were either wrong or obvious. Then everyone had a good laugh
and went back to the lab bench for some more grinding, reductionist
science, walled off from their colleagues in adjoining disciplines,
who were themselves grinding away on their own tiny corners of the
universe [...] What's different now is a
feeling in the air. Even the most hard-boiled mainstream scientists
are beginning to acknowledge that reductionism may not be powerful
enough to solve all the great mysteries we're facing: cancer,
consciousness, the origin of life, the resilience of the ecosystem,
AIDS, global warming, the functioning of a cell, the ebb and flow of
the economy [...] What makes all these
unsolved problems so vexing is their decentralized, dynamic
character, in which enormous numbers of components keep changing
their state from moment to moment, looping back on one another in
ways that can't be studied by examining any one part in isolation.
In such cases the whole is surely not equal to the sum of the parts.
These phenomena, like others in the universe, are fundamentally
nonlinear.(2)
One of the first significant scientific developments to come out of
studies of complexity came in meteorology in the early 2000s. Another
mathematician, David Orrell, sparked off a debate in this field when he
put forward the idea that errors in weather forecasts were not
attributable to chaos but rather to errors in the models. Further, he
claimed that errors in the models are insurmountable because of the
complexity of the underlying system; unlike chaos, complexity is
incomputable.
If his argument has made inroads in meteorology, mainstream economics (which
uses similar models for similar systems) has mostly sailed over the
entire issue so far. Obviously, there are immense political implications
for mainstream economics that are not shared by meteorology and that
might present an incentive for maintaining the status quo. This
leads to a strange divergence in which, out of two mathematical models
sharing similar physics, methods and limitations, one is known to not be
reliable enough to decide on buying waterproof clothes for a trek
planned in a week, whereas the other still settles public policy
decisions designed to affect millions of lives.
Orrell addresses the limitations of mathematical models with regard to
predicting complex systems such as the economy, health or the climate in
his book, The Future of Everything.(3)
He first distinguishes between chaos and complexity. One of their main
differences is that there is no order in chaos, whereas order emerges
spontaneously in complex systems. And indeed, without any central will
planning it, order exists in nature, in living organisms and in
economies. It emerges out of the multiple relationships and their
feedback effects between the various elements of the systems, as these
feedbacks create an ever-adjusting balance. Another emerging property of
some complex systems is adaptation.
Such properties of complex systems are difficult for models to capture
because they are alien to reductionism. Order and adaptation are
displayed by a system as a whole and cannot be understood under the same
rules that govern the relationships between the individual elements of
the systems. Think of the human brain: drawing a map of all its neurons
and knowing how one interacts with another still does not capture
intelligence or memory. Think also of Adam Smith’s metaphor of the
"invisible hand"—the ability of the free market to allocate resources
and serve society despite the fact that each agent merely seeks his own
interest.
Reductionism as a way of understanding and modelling complex systems is
therefore a scientific error: a method which worked in many physical
instances but which was erroneously transposed to fields where it was
not appropriate. Further, if reductionism is a mistaken approach merely
due to its obfuscation of the holistic nature of complex systems, it is
made even worse by the fact that even the individual, nonlinear
relationships between the parts themselves are difficult to capture
mathematically. For instance, there are no equations for clouds or for
their exact relationships with the oceans, and thus climate models must
use approximations.
In economics, models must assume that economic agents act rationally or
tend towards maximum efficiency. Yet, people do make irrational economic
decisions. This can affect the validity of the models enormously. Orrell
explains that models of complex systems are very sensitive to small
errors in the approximate equations, notably because these systems are
host to an extremely delicate balance between opposing forces and
feedback mechanisms, where a slight imbalance in their representation
has big effects on the accuracy of the models’ projections.
Approximations are thus one of the main sources of forecast error—an
error that grows with time as the system adopts a path that departs from
the one projected.
Put another way, computer programs must necessarily follow pre-determined,
well-defined rules, whereas the behaviours of humans or of the natural
world are often based on perpetually evolving rules, or on no rules at
all. This means that the world within a model can only evolve towards
the outcome set by the rules contained in the program, a mere
description of what would happen if those rules were followed in the
real world, holding all else constant.
Finally, a scientific theory’s validity lies in its ability to survive
testing, and models can only be tested against past experience. If such
tests can work for simpler problems, they cannot work for complex
systems where non-linearity and emergent properties such as adaptation
mean that the past is no indication of the future. Even if the models
are set to "predict" past data, they are still blind about what is to
come. The test is therefore hopelessly flawed: predictions can always
succeed in predicting the past, but this test is irrelevant if history
does not repeat itself. And without a worthy test, any theory can seem
to work.
All in all, complexity theory gives us a more rigorous insight into what
was before a more intuitive perception of the difficulty of accurately
forecasting the economy, as it addresses the very mathematical aspects
of the issue. Now, knowing this, what should be our course of action? To
keep making predictions that we know cannot be saved from error, and
nevertheless act on their basis, or stop using them and adopt a more
stochastic approach where we would use the available information, aware
of the limits to our knowledge? If "the study of the characteristics of
complex dynamic systems is showing us exactly why limited knowledge is
unavoidable [and] confronts us with the limits of human understanding,"(4)
learning our limits is then an actual scientific discovery. To disregard
this advancement would be foolish and unscientific. And yet, it seems
that this is what economic forecasters are paid to do by our most
powerful public institutions.
In the land of the blind, the one-eyed man is king
Predictions of the future are never anything but projections of
present automatic processes and procedures, that is, of occurrences that
are likely to come to pass if men do not act and if nothing unexpected
happens; every action, for better or worse, and every accident
necessarily destroys the whole pattern in whose frame the prediction
moves and where it finds its evidence. –Hannah Arendt(5)
Quantitative financier, former Wall Street trader and now bestselling
author Nassim Taleb also took mainstream economics to task in his book,
The Black Swan,(6)
which was translated into dozens of languages and was named one of the
12 most influential books of the post-WW2 period by the Sunday Times.(7)
Taleb made a fortune during the 2008 financial crisis betting against
the models, as he understood that they discounted the "improbable" risk
of systemic failure. He now uses his fame to good cause, warning us
about the folly of guiding entire economies with wrongheaded economic
models and theories. He is most emphatic about the dangers presented by
economic forecasters, suggesting that "[a]nyone who causes harm by
forecasting should be treated as either a fool or a liar. Some
forecasters cause more damage to society than criminals."
Taleb points to Paul Samuelson as the father of mainstream economics as
it is currently taught in academia. Samuelson’s textbook, Economics:
An Introductory Analysis, was first published in 1948 as one of the
first American textbooks to explain the principles of Keynesian
economics, and led to today’s intensified use of quantitative methods in
economic analysis. As of today, his book still reigns in colleges and is
now in its 19th edition. Taleb’s reflection on Samuelson’s legacy is
unequivocal:
In orthodox economics, rationality became a straitjacket.
Platonified economists ignored the fact that people might prefer to
do something other than maximize their economic interests. This led
to mathematical techniques such as "maximization," or "optimization,"
on which Paul Samuelson built much of his work.
[...] I would not be the first to say that this optimization
set back social science by reducing it from the intellectual and
reflective discipline that it was becoming to an attempt at an
"exact science." By "exact science," I mean a second-rate
engineering problem for those who want to pretend that they are in
the physics department—so-called physics envy. In other words, an
intellectual fraud.
Taleb argues against the Nobel Prize in economics for the damage it
has done through its beatification of mistaken ideas about prediction
and risk management; incorrect economic theories can be devastating and
should never become gospel in such an uncertain environment. Forecasting
methods create a false sense of security, or worse, send people in the
wrong direction. Colleges then exacerbate the problem by teaching these
Nobel-approved ideas as orthodoxy.(8)
The "Ludic fallacy" is what Taleb calls the misuse of statistics that
work in casino games to model real-life situations and their risk
prospects mathematically. He refutes the validity of predictive models
in complex situations where these statistical methods do not work,
pointing out that the mathematical purity of such models fails to take
into account certain key ideas such as the impossibility of possessing
all relevant information and the fact that small unknown variations in
the data can have a huge impact.
The rise of scientism
The trouble with the world is that the stupid are cocksure and the
intelligent are full of doubt. –Bertrand Russell, logician and
pacifist, co-author of the Russell-Einstein manifesto.
One hundred percent. –Ben Bernanke, chairman of the Federal
Reserve, on his confidence that the Federal Reserve will control
inflation.
Doubt and epistemology have become anathema to modern (or scientific)
central planning, if only because they disturb the illusion that things
can be properly handled.(9)
Yet one of the fathers of Western philosophy, Socrates, illuminated a
timeless principle when he declared that what he knew was the fact of
his own ignorance (a correction to the extravagance that we can know
something truly or completely), and when he considered himself wiser
than another man because he did not fancy himself as knowing what he did
not know. For Socrates, doubt and curiosity were characteristics of the
wise.
It is curiosity that propelled the brightest minds of the past to
question myths and dogmas. With the might of the scientific method,
religion and superstition were deposed along with their explanations of
many phenomena in fields such as astronomy, chemistry or physics. Come
the 19th century, what still remained for human reason to solve and what
still aroused curiosity was society itself and its behaviours. And
intoxicated by the successes of Newtonian natural sciences so far, it
was no surprise that a few clouded minds soon prescribed the same
methods to explain "social physics."
Hence came Auguste Comte (1798-1857), the father of sociology (originally
coined "physique sociale") and an associate of Henri de Saint-Simon, the
French early socialist. Recognising that the natural sciences had
accomplished so much but that humanity remained clueless about social
problems, Comte believed there was a next and ultimate phase of social
evolution which was yet to come, namely Positivism (referring to the
possibility of explaining all things, including the social, with the
help of the scientific method). Comte realized that sociology was a more
"complex" science, but believed that its problems could be solved using
the same procedures that solved less complex phenomena. So in the
Positivist age, through a social science based on quantitative and
mathematical thinking, which he considered the centrepiece of all
science, Comte saw a future world where the age of abstract rights (the
Enlightenment era) would be replaced by a more modern period where
society would be centrally planned by a scientific elite, empowered by
its mastery of a new synthesizing science of man. Individual rights
would be obsolete, replaced by duties in a world where experts "know
best."
Comte’s beliefs did have a profound influence on scientific and
sociological thinking. If his Positivist religion gained little
traction, his idea that society can be fixed through the scientific
method beguiled many and is now widely held. Yet strangely, there never
was any evidence to demonstrate that the traditional methods of the
natural sciences were fit for examining complex social phenomena. It has
just been assumed. This creates another strange situation in which those
who believe most fervently in the power of science are proceeding under
an assumption which was never scientifically demonstrated.
In a way, Comte invented modern central planning. Marx and Hegel, among
others, were likely influenced by him (or by his mentor St-Simon) and
after their theories had spread, Positivists soon described themselves
as Marxists.(10) On the
belief that social problems could be fixed under an empirical "scientific"
approach, grandiose plans of social reorganization were pushed forward
in Europe and in the United States, enjoying support among social
scientists and progressive leaders. Socialism became hugely popular and
took over several countries. Woodrow Wilson supported eugenics, and many
others praised Mussolini and/or the communists. These were instances of
groundbreaking social engineering experiments after all. Those who
opposed them were living in the past, fighting against progress and
solutions to human ills.
No matter how different in practical terms the kinds of central planning
are now (Keynesianism, neo-classical economics, socialism, etc.), they
still all spring from the same root: the idea that society can be
mathematically reconstructed like a mechanical phenomenon and that the
traditional methods of the natural sciences can be applied to fix its
problems as if society were a laboratory-like controllable environment.
Scientism is not only the ghost behind socialism, but hides behind all
forms of contemporary central planning. It has already caused much harm,
but the worst may still be ahead. Economics, as a social science
connecting all and everything, is a hegemonic instrument. As the elder
Rothschild said, "give me control of a nation’s money and I care not who
makes her laws." Economics is Comte’s "physique sociale." Once it is
widely believed that in its mastery or domestication by a select few
lies the solution to the world’s every problem, liberty becomes a
secondary issue, as the march towards utopia must prevail.
This involves enormous implications for the fate of freedom (or abstract
rights) and since this discussion is inevitably to be considered on
scientific grounds, Hayek also sought to draw our attention back to
epistemology, for through our ignorance of the limits of science, we
expose ourselves to destroying much that we hold dear. Hayek’s final
book, The Fatal Conceit, addresses the erroneous belief that man
can shape society according to his wishes. As he observed, many
progressives, socialists and central planners would have avoided their
action plans if they could have really known the results in advance.
The Pretence of Knowledge
If we are wise, recent developments may help us to rediscover the role
of the economist as a holistic observer rather than as a quantitative
advisor. Perhaps the economist can then reclaim his credibility and
assume a useful role which will not put him in a position where he is
expected to blindly advise the king on what to do because he pretends
that he can read the future. But to paraphrase MIT’s Ricardo Caballero,
macroeconomics as a field of study has been transformed over the decades
from a verbal discussion of the real world to a discussion based on
quantitative analysis of an alternate world.(11)
This transformation appears difficult to reverse, as "modern"
macroeconomics models are now at the core of economics faculties and
their use has become a precondition for publication in academic journals
since the 70s.(12)
Yet, the 2008 financial crisis should strike us as evidence of the
failure of mainstream macroeconomics. As late as February 2008, Ben
Bernanke was still
claiming that "my baseline outlook involves a period of sluggish
growth, followed by a somewhat stronger pace of growth starting later
this year as the effects of monetary and fiscal stimulus begin to be
felt." So today, when quantitative easing programs prompted by
mathematical models of the economy are championed by the same person who
did not see the train coming from ten yards away, how confident can we
be about his latest prediction that he will know how to control the
dangers of inflation?
Unfortunately, not very. Complex systems are characterized by
decentralized, bottom-up governance. Order and direction of the whole
are the result, but not the design, of the various relationships between
the elements. Top-down management forced upon complex systems hampers
their normal functioning, if only because the rule-makers cannot gain
mastery of all the relevant, dispersed and elusive information which
would be necessary to carry out decisions that would match the system’s
holistic "intelligence." Therein lie the conflicts between legislation
and common law, between central planning and spontaneous order, between
authoritarianism and liberty. From this viewpoint, the re-emergent
Austrian School of economics stands alone in its understanding of the
benefits of decentralizing social and economic decisions.(13)
My argument would not be complete without a return to what is perhaps
the most eloquent exposition of the shortcomings of blindly applied
quantitative methods in economics, namely
Hayek’s Nobel Prize Lecture. Since I cannot better communicate
Hayek’s points with my own words, my initial idea was to reproduce a few
important excerpts. Obviously, though, there were too many, and I
elected to reproduce only his introduction, which could just as well
have been written today.
My first hope is that readers who are unfamiliar with this lecture will
be prompted to read it. My second and highest hope is that the lessons
of prudence, humility and sound science which Hayek hoped to teach us
will finally gain traction in an era when they are needed more than ever
and when our understanding of complex phenomena is now more in sync
with Hayek than it was when he delivered his timeless lecture in Sweden,
decades ago:
Prize Lecture
Lecture to the memory of Alfred Nobel, December 11, 1974
The Pretence of Knowledge
The particular occasion of this lecture, combined with the chief
practical problem which economists have to face today, have made the
choice of its topic almost inevitable. On the one hand the still
recent establishment of the Nobel Memorial Prize in Economic Science
marks a significant step in the process by which, in the opinion of
the general public, economics has been conceded some of the dignity
and prestige of the physical sciences. On the other hand, the
economists are at this moment called upon to say how to extricate
the free world from the serious threat of accelerating inflation
which, it must be admitted, has been brought about by policies which
the majority of economists recommended and even urged governments to
pursue. We have indeed at the moment little cause for pride: as a
profession we have made a mess of things.
It seems to me that this failure of the economists to guide policy
more successfully is closely connected with their propensity to
imitate as closely as possible the procedures of the brilliantly
successful physical sciences—an attempt which in our field may lead
to outright error. It is an approach which has come to be described
as the "scientistic" attitude—an attitude which, as I defined it
some thirty years ago, "is decidedly unscientific in the true sense
of the word, since it involves a mechanical and uncritical
application of habits of thought to fields different from those in
which they have been formed." I want today to begin by explaining
how some of the gravest errors of recent economic policy are a
direct consequence of this scientistic error.
Notes
1. Science, Philosophy and Religion: A Symposium, published by
the Conference on Science, Philosophy and Religion in Their Relation to
the Democratic Way of Life, Inc., New York (1941).
2. Strogatz, S. H., Sync: The Emerging Science of Spontaneous Order,
Hyperion, 352 pages (2003).
3. Orrell, D., The Future of Everything: The Science of Prediction,
Basic Books, 464 pages (2006).
4. Cilliers, P., "Why We Cannot Know Complex Things Completely,"
Emergence, 4(1/2), 77-84 (2002). His optimistic comments about
models, though, appear misguided, if only because he seems to believe
that the models could become as complex as the systems themselves. This
seems an erroneous stance since increasing a model’s resolution usually
adds to uncertainty, as every agent and feedback effect cannot be
precisely represented through data or mathematical equations (such as
clouds or human feelings)5. Harendt, H., On Violence, Houghton
Mifflin Harcourt, 106 pages (1970). Pages 6-8 are of particular interest
to the subject of predictions and scientific central planning.
6. Taleb, N. N., The Black Swan: The Impact of the Highly Improbable,
Random House, 366 pages (2007).
7. Appleyard, B., "Books that Helped to Change the World," The Sunday
Times (July 19, 2009).
8. Cox, A., "Blame
Nobel for crisis, says author of 'Black Swan'," Reuters (September
28, 2010).
9. The inspired idea to juxtapose the two citations above is from Adam
Sharp, from
Wealth Daily.
10. See for instance Curtis, M., Marxism: The Inner Dialogues,
volume 1 (2nd edition), pp. 27-31.
11. Caballero, R. J., Macroeconomics after the Crisis: Time to Deal
with the Pretense-of-Knowledge Syndrome, MIT Department of Economics
Working Paper No. 10-16 (September 27, 2010).
12. See this October 6, 2010
Forefront interview with former Federal Reserve governor Laurence
Meyer.
13. Austrian School economists were notably early in apprehending that
complex systems are incomputable when they fought the economic
calculation debate in the early 20th century.
----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
*
Jean-Hugho Lapointe
is a lawyer. He holds a certificate in business administration
from Université Laval. |