THE RATIONAL ARGUMENTATOR |
Meaningful and Vacuous “Privilege” |
Sanford Ikeda's concise and insightful lists of 14 common
fallacies about the free market (available in two
installments from The Freeman
here and
here) motivate careful thought about the commonly used
and misused term “privilege” and the conflations in which it
can result. In discussing the second fallacy regarding the
free market, that it is identical to a system where the
government grants special privileges to businesses, Dr.
Ikeda writes that “People sometimes define ‘privilege' as any advantage a person or group may have over others.
Certainly such advantages exist today and would exist in a
free market—you may be born into a wealthy family or have
superior drive and resourcefulness—but these advantages are
consistent with the absence of privilege in the libertarian
sense, as long as you acquired such advantages without fraud
or the initiation of physical violence against the person or
property of others.”
Indeed, the increasingly common usage
of the term “privilege” to mean any advantage whatsoever
eviscerates it of any genuine meaning it once had. This
problem in today's discourse spreads far beyond discussions
of connections between businesses and governments.
Certainly, the very fact that one individual is different
from another—with a different set of experiences,
different physique, different knowledge, and even different
standing room at any particular time—provides that
individual with opportunities that the other lacks, while
rendering him or her limited in ways that the other is not.
Unfortunately, this trivial fact is increasingly being
misconstrued in some circles to suggest vile inequities
arising out of innocuous human differences.
People who have
not aggressed against, or even demeaned or ridiculed, anyone
are increasingly being identified as “privileged” simply for
belonging to broadly and crudely defined groups—be it all
people of European descent, all males, or even all non-overweight
people (witness the pseudo-concept of “thin privilege”) or
people who are not disabled. (“Ableism” is apparently an
emerging sin in the vocabulary of the increasingly militant
and vitriolic collectivistic “social justice” movement—which is about neither true individual-oriented justice nor
the preservation of a civilized and tolerant society.) Such
a vacuously expansive view of privilege is a tremendous
insult to the true victims of coercive privilege throughout
history—from slaves in all eras, to women who in prior
eras were denied suffrage and property rights, to the
freethinkers and forbears of liberty and reason, whose
voices were too often snuffed out by the arbitrary power of
absolute monarchs and theocrats in the pre-Enlightenment
world.
|
“People who have
not aggressed against, or even demeaned or ridiculed, anyone
are increasingly being identified as ‘privileged’
simply for
belonging to broadly and crudely defined groups—be it all
people of European descent, all males, or even all non-overweight
people (witness the pseudo-concept of ‘thin privilege’) or
people who are not disabled.” |
Thomas Jefferson, an opponent of privilege in its
meaningful sense, put it best when he expressed in his 1826
letter to Roger C. Weightman “the palpable truth, that
the mass of mankind has not been born with saddles on their
backs, nor a favored few booted and spurred, ready to ride
legitimately, by the grace of god.” Jefferson was a staunch
opponent of the coercive privilege that enabled some to gain
artificial advantages by restricting others from pursuing
life-improving courses of action. Accidents of birth, or
special lobbying skills, should not, in a just system,
enable a person to acquire prerogatives which could not be
earned through the free, peaceful exercise of that person's
abilities. Jefferson saw the future and strength of the
American republic in the hoped-for emergence of a “natural
aristocracy of talent and virtue”—people who, when allowed
the liberty to flourish through honest work and competition,
would become role models for others solely through their
examples. This natural aristocracy would not need force to
maintain its prominence, because the traits of the most
knowledgeable, most industrious, and most virtuous people
will be emulated by any who earnestly seek to improve their
own lives and who have the freedom to acquire knowledge and
make their own decisions.
Yet Jefferson's natural aristocracy would be denounced as
an example of horrid “privilege” by the “social justice”
types—simply due to the necessarily unequal distribution
of outcomes on a free market of open and honest production,
competition, and cooperation. After all, not everyone can
originate the same ideas at the same time. Not everyone can
take advantage of the same opportunity for entrepreneurial
profit, whose attainment, as economist Israel Kirzner
demonstrated in
Competition and Entrepreneurship, arises out of
alertness to opportunities that others have missed. Kirzner
writes that “Because the participants in
[a] market are less than omniscient, there are likely to
exist, at any given time, a multitude of opportunities that
have not yet been taken advantage of. Sellers may have sold
for prices lower than the prices which were in fact
obtainable… Buyers may have bought for prices higher than
the lowest prices needed to secure what they are buying…”
(p. 41). Would it be an example of unacceptable “privilege” for
an alert entrepreneur to remedy such an arbitrage
opportunity and thereby bring otherwise-unrealized value to
consumers?
Yes, the free exercise of human abilities will produce
outcomes where some people will have some advantages over
some others (while, of course, leaving fully open the
possibility that those very others will have their own
distinct advantages, obtained through hard work, knowledge,
or sheer luck). But, as long as coercion is not involved in
securing and maintaining those advantages, the people
endowed with them are not “booted and spurred” to ride the
rest of us. As Dr. Ikeda points out, the differences among
people are a source of strength harnessed by the free
market: “The free market gives you an incentive to profit
from associating with and learning from others who might be
very different from you, who operate outside your normal
social networks.” By incentivizing and facilitating these
interactions, the free market encourages greater tolerance,
understanding, and visible societal heterogeneity of the
sort that constitutes the best safeguard against truly
heinous oppressions based on collectivistic stereotypes.
Instead of condemning others as being too “privileged”
simply on account of innocuous differences, it is far more
productive to think about how those differences can help one
achieve one's own values through honest, peaceful, and
productive interaction, cooperation, and exchange.
|
|
From the same author |
▪
Feedback Loops and Individual Self-Determination
(no
316 – November 15, 2013)
▪
Review of Edward W. Younkins's Exploring
Capitalist Fiction
(no
315 – October 15, 2013)
▪
War in the Middle East is Inherently Collectivist
(no
314 – Sept. 15, 2013)
▪
Against Monsanto, For GMOs
(no
313 – August 15, 2013)
▪
In the Face of Universal Surveillance: PRISM and the
Litmus Test for Liberty
(no
312 – June 15, 2013)
▪
More...
|
|
First written appearance of the
word 'liberty,' circa 2300 B.C. |
Le Québécois Libre
Promoting individual liberty, free markets and voluntary
cooperation since 1998.
|
|