To be black in the United States is to have been
dealt a bad hand.
African Americans
are, among other things, poorer, less educated and less healthy than
their white compatriots. While the underlying reasons are myriad, there
is no doubt that the primary root cause is slavery. Immediately before
the Civil War,
almost 90%
of the American black population was enslaved, which means that there
may not currently be a single African American with ancestors in the
antebellum United States who is not descended from a slave. Even after
the war, formal legal equality was achieved only when the Supreme Court
finally struck down the abhorrent
system of segregation in 1965.
The condition of American blacks would be incalculably better had
slavery never existed on US soil, leading to occasional talk of
reparations. In 1999, one group called for an indemnity of no less than
$777 trillion, or
more than 31 times the planet’s entire GDP
for that year (in fairness, the amount was to be paid not just by the US
but by the entire Western world). Since these kinds of outlandish
demands have been the public image of the calls for reparations, it was
with skepticism that I approached “The Case for Reparations,”
a much-talked about cover piece from the June issue of The Atlantic
authored by Ta-Nehisi Coates. To my surprise, the 16,000-word essay was
a delight. In elegant prose and with a masterful command of the
historical facts, Coates argues that today’s problems are due not merely
to slavery but also to racist modern-day government policy.
So You Wanna Buy a House?
The article describes the practice of “redlining,” under which the
Federal Housing Administration refused to insure mortgages in
neighbourhoods that failed to meet certain criteria—which, curiously,
black areas never did. It thereby locked African Americans out of
mainstream financing and pushed them toward alternatives such as
“contract buying,” under which title passed to the borrower only once
the loan was repaid. If he missed just one payment, a borrower could be
expelled without compensation and lose the money he put down. The same
property could thus be sold and repossessed multiple times in quick
succession. The resulting scar is still visible today: Coates cites
research showing that in Chicago, “black families making $100,000
typically live in the kinds of neighborhoods inhabited by white families
making $30,000.” Other examples of state-sponsored discrimination
include exempting predominantly black trades from Social Security and
unemployment benefits (though not, presumably, from the corresponding
taxes).
Coates’ call for “reparations” uses a peculiar definition of the word:
“the full acceptance of our collective biography and its consequences.”
In other words, “a national reckoning” that will help Americans
understand the darker side of their history. I would enthusiastically
support such a process. It could bring about an America where a
politician who claimed that the Founding Fathers “worked tirelessly to
end slavery”
would be laughed out of office; where a black president is criticized on
his appalling record
rather than ludicrous and irrelevant claims regarding his
ancestry
and
religion;
and where
the 42% of white people
who still associate the Confederate flag with “southern pride” instead
of racism finally see the light.
While Coates’ definition of reparations is something of a cop-out, in
several
follow-up
pieces,
he asserts that blacks are owed financial compensation, which is
consistent with the more usual meaning. He does not, however, argue for
reparations for slavery at large, which is best since the notion fails
to pass the laugh test.
Several rebuttals
explain why, though frankly they are refuting a straw-man argument that
Coates did not actually make. The gist of the case against such payments
is that they
are unworkable
in practical terms—sorting out who would pay how much to whom would be
impossible—and devoid
of any legal or moral basis. Slavery’s perpetrators and victims are long
dead and all that can be done is to fully acknowledge that they are part
of the legacy of the past.
L’État, c’est qui?
Coates’ actual case is nuanced, arguing instead for reparations to be
paid to today’s blacks for the harms that they have suffered due to
policies much more recent than slavery. While his argument is
multi-faceted, two key points stand out. First, he thinks that the funds
should be paid from the US treasury (and so by all taxpayers of whatever
colour). Second, he notes that many of the victims of these policies,
such as those he profiles in his article, are still alive and have
suffered clearly identifiable and personal harm.
Coates’ argument that reparations should be paid out of the public purse
is
as follows:
The governments of the United States of
America—local, state and federal—are deeply implicated in enslavement,
Jim Crow, redlining, New Deal racism, terrorism, ghettoization, housing
segregation. The fact that one’s ancestors were not slave-traders or
that one arrived here in 1980 is irrelevant. I did not live in New York
when the city railroaded the Central Park Five. But my tax dollars will
pay for the settlement. That is because a state is more than the natural
lives, or occupancy, of its citizens.
The problem is that this reasoning conceives of the state as a distinct
entity with its own existence, capable of independent action. But the
state is nothing more than a collection of individuals and cannot
“outlive” its individual citizens because, like a corporation, it exists
only as a legal fiction. The wealth of the “state” is merely the wealth
of today’s taxpayers. So the question is, is it fair for those taxpayers
to bear the burden of reparations? In other words, is “American
taxpayers” a reasonable proxy for “Beneficiaries of Racist Policy?”
|
“When a person is harmed in
some way, the appropriate mechanism for redress is not a
program of reparations, but instead legal action by that
individual against the transgressor.” |
Compare a man who immigrated to Denver in 2012 to a white resident of
Atlanta whose family tree includes slaveholders. It is difficult to
think of any benefits that an immigrant to an area where slavery
never existed—and
only 5%
of the population is black—could have obtained from racist practices
such as redlining. In contrast, the Atlantan’s situation would likely be
very different had his ancestors never owned other human beings. These
are extreme examples, but the point is that there is massive variation
in the degree to which Americans are better off thanks to state
discrimination. To make them all liable and to base the extent of their
liability on the amount of taxes that they pay makes little sense.
Coates ignores the obvious—and preferable—alternative: Hold the people
who committed the wrongdoing accountable. Make them liable for
the harm that they caused. The
Central Park Five
case that Coates cites is a perfect example: Five black and Hispanic
youths wrongfully convicted of raping a Central Park jogger who settled
a lawsuit against New York City for $40 million. But why should the
city’s taxpayers bear that burden, rather than the police officers and
the prosecutors who steamrolled the innocent? Why shouldn’t the actual
wrongdoers be accountable both financially and, if appropriate,
criminally? That should be the starting point for this
discussion.
Had Coates explained that the architects of redlining are long dead and
as an exception we should therefore consider the imperfect alternative
of drawing on public funds, his position would be defensible. But his
argument is instead that something called “the state” is responsible and
that everyone who pays taxes to the US treasury should therefore be
liable in proportion to his or her tax bill. That position is untenable.
Coates makes the second point I mention above—that the victims of racism
are still alive—to defuse the objection that everyone who deserves
compensation is dead. After reading his piece, while I think that Coates
is mistaken as to who should pay for reparations, in my view he
is on solid ground as to who should receive them. But he fails to
realize one consequence of his insight that injured persons remain
alive: When a person is harmed in some way, the appropriate mechanism
for redress is not a program of reparations, but instead legal action by
that individual against the transgressor. In other words, the people who
were redlined out of decent neighbourhoods should sue those who wronged
them.
Justice for All
The obvious objection to this suggestion is
that a lawsuit—especially against the government—will be slow and
expensive. The best defence strategy would not be some legal doctrine,
but simply dragging out the process until the aging plaintiffs run out
of either money or time. And the obvious solution is to simplify and
streamline the legal system so that any adult can, without professional
assistance or any unusual amount of time, money or intelligence, seek
justice against anyone else.
I am fully aware of the magnitude of what I am proposing: “Just fix the
legal system” is only slightly less utopian than “Just stop the
violence.” But making up for centuries of discrimination, injustice and
abuse is an aspiration born of big dreams. So why not dream equally big
when crafting the solution? Rebuilding the American legal system to work
for everyone would be a massive undertaking, but with an equally massive
payoff. In a world where any competent adult could bring a lawsuit to a
successful conclusion—no matter who the defendant—the deep-pocketed
would no longer act with de facto impunity, secure in the knowledge that
to take them on in court would be self-defeating madness. Under the
current system,
four lawyers in five
admit to turning away clients if their case is not cost-effective and
state that high costs force them to settle cases that, on the merits,
should go to trial. The biggest beneficiaries of a legal process that
worked would be the poor of all colours, who would have a means to seek
redress against government, big business or anyone else who injured
them.
The high cost of a lawsuit is not a problem only for those seeking their
day in court. Lawsuits filed by wealthy plaintiffs exclusively to
silence their critics by forcing expensive litigation upon them are so
common that they have been given a catchy acronym:
SLAPP
(Strategic lawsuit against public participation). A system in which both
prosecuting and defending a case was relatively simple could
eliminate such tactics—indeed, it would mitigate the risk of frivolous
lawsuits in general.
At its core, the case that Ta-Nehisi Coates makes for reparations is a
case for justice. And if it is justice that is needed, then the best
solution is to make it available to the greatest number possible so that
all wrongs—of whatever nature and inflicted on whomever—have a real
chance of being righted. The best way to achieve that objective is not
yet another top-down government program, but a sweeping overhaul of the
mechanism by which individuals themselves seek justice. Fix the legal
system, and you fix a lot more than Coates ever imagined.
|
|
From the same author |
▪
The Great War's Legacy, a Century On
(no
323 – June 15, 2014)
▪
Is Justice Compatible with the Rule of Law?
(no
322 – May 15, 2014)
▪
The 2014 Quebec Election: This Time, It Mattered
(no
321 – April 15, 2014)
▪
The Belle Knox Controversy and How to Make the World
a Better Place
(no
320 – March 15, 2014)
▪
Civil Forfeiture Laws: Legalizing Theft?
(no
319 – February 15, 2014)
▪
More...
|
|
First written appearance of the
word 'liberty,' circa 2300 B.C. |
Le Québécois Libre
Promoting individual liberty, free markets and voluntary
cooperation since 1998.
|
|