Frank Knight's Economic and Social Theology |
Frank Hyneman Knight (1885-1972), who spent most of his career at the
University of Chicago, where he became a founder of the
Chicago School,
was, from the early 1920s until the late 1950s, one of the world’s most
influential economists.
Milton
Friedman,
George
Stigler
and
James M.
Buchanan
numbered among his students and acolytes. A British economist who taught
at Chicago,
Ronald
Coase,
wasn’t a student of Knight’s; nonetheless, Coase credited Knight as a
major influence upon his thinking.(1)
In 1957 Knight received the American Economic Association’s Francis A.
Walker Award, which was (the AEA subsequently discontinued it) conferred
“not more frequently than once every five years to the living [American]
economist who in the judgment of the awarding body has during his career
made the greatest contribution to economics.”
Knight clarified significant problems of mainstream economic theory and
policy. (As we’ll see, he regarded economic and social matters as at
best imperfectly comprehensible; not infrequently, they were unsolvable
and even unfathomable.) Today he’s best remembered for his book Risk
Uncertainty and Profit (1921).(2)
As time passed, he became more a systematic theologian than an applied
economist.(3)
Economists today typically know or care little about the later Knight;
but it was in this role that the key figures in the Chicago school such
as Friedman and Stigler encountered him and through which he exerted his
greatest and most enduring influence.
If Knight were alive today his views would likely mystify faculty and
students. In the classroom, as Don Patinkin observed,(4)
Knight regularly undertook “long digressions on the nature of man and
society – and God.” His faith was profound. Yet by the standards of his
time and ours, it was quite unconventional. He didn’t consider himself a
Christian: indeed, throughout his academic career he openly (and
occasionally publicly) disparaged “traditional religion.”(5)
He did, however, spend his formative years in a devout family and pious
community; and although as a young man he left in order to pursue his
studies (first at Milligan College, a small Christian institution in
east Tennessee, and later at Cornell University in upstate New York), in
important respects his family’s and childhood community’s ethical and
spiritual precepts never left him. Perhaps that’s why in 1945 he and a
theologian, Thornton W. Merriam, co-wrote a book entitled The
Economic Order and Religion; similarly, in 1950 he dubbed his
presidential address to the AEA as his “sermon” to the profession. And
perhaps that’s why his ashes have been interred in the crypt of the
First Unitarian Church of Chicago.(6)
How, exactly, was Knight essentially a theologian? He insisted that the
core social and economic problem, and hence the economist’s essential
task, was the “discovery and definition of values – a moral, not to say a
religious, problem.” Indeed, Knight contended that myriad “economic
problems” are mere material symptoms and consequences of a single
spiritual cause – namely man’s innately sinful nature.(7)
More specifically, and according to Nelson,
despite all his outward hostility to Christianity, Knight’s own
[economic] theology … follows surprisingly closely in the Calvinist
understanding of Christian faith. … Human beings in Knight’s view are in
fact corrupt creatures whose actual behavior in the world corresponds
closely to the biblical understanding of the consequences of original
sin.
Richard Boyd demonstrates that Knight’s conception of economics has
“much more in common with [the Christianity of St Augustine of Hippo]
than it does with the [rationalism and utilitarianism of the]
Enlightenment.” Martin Luther, originally an Augustinian monk who came
to despise the rational and mechanical (as he regarded it) theology of
Thomas Aquinas, revived Augustine’s earlier and more pessimistic (with
respect to man’s sinful life in this fallen world) theology. Boyd adds
that Knight’s worldview thus differed fundamentally and perhaps
diametrically from Adam Smith’s, Friedrich Hayek’s and Milton Friedman’s
– all of whom believed, sometimes fervently, in the great “benefits
of progress, development and economic efficiency”.(8)
The Augustinian, Calvinist and Knightian view rejects the mainstream’s
“progressive” vision. The mainstream is utilitarian: the individual
attempts to maximise his own happiness; and politicians, ably advised by
progressive economists, use specific means (economic policy, scientific
management, etc.) to achieve a particular end (the continuous
improvement of material conditions, and eventual universal happiness,
here on earth). “In such matters and in coming down on the Calvinist
rather than the progressive and rationalist side,” Nelson concludes in
Economics as Religion: From Samuelson to Chicago and Beyond,
“Knight was a secular kind of Protestant fundamentalist, reacting
against the thinking of virtually the entire economics profession of his
time.”
From this theological contention sprang fundamental practical
consequences. Not only, for example, did Knight’s theology contradict
Progressive
(hereafter with a lower-case “p”) aspirations for the “value-free”
scientific management of economy and society: it utterly rejected them.(9)
Knight always doubted and often flatly denied that economic and social
engineering could possibly succeed in any meaningful sense. In man’s
fumbling hands, he believed, reason is a frail and unreliable
instrument. Specifically, the baser elements of fallen human nature
always corrupt it; for this reason, it’s usually prone to gross and
sometimes greatly damaging error.
Although Knight’s expression of this view in overtly theological terms
was unusual, it was hardly original. Quite the contrary, it’s anything
but novel. Knight readily acknowledged that this pessimistic view of
human nature and reason is simply the classic (albeit viewed through
non-liturgical Protestant lens) Christian view of fallen human beings
beset by original sin. It’s a long-standing Christian tradition: private
property, the marketplace and largely unfettered (apart from a few basic
prohibitions against aggression, fraud, etc.) trading and investing are
unfortunate but nonetheless necessary concessions to the pervasive
presence of evil in the world. In the past (that is, in the Garden of
Eden) there was no and in the future (namely in heaven) there will be no
private property (or, for that matter, government). Meanwhile, in this
world, stable and secure rights to property and the active pursuit of
profit are means to maintain a semblance of peace and order. Orthodox
Christianity has long contended, in Richard Schlatter’s words, that
“since the Fall the natures of men, all of them depraved, make necessary
… the division [into private ownership] of property …”(10)
Viewing matters through a non-liturgical Protestant lens, Knight
emphatically denied that an anointed priesthood of “expert” economists
could possibly escape the shackles of the general human condition.
Progressive economists, in other words, were depraved sinners just like
everybody else; as a result, they were equally prone – nay, given their
tendency towards hubris, even more likely than the humble generalist and
layperson – to fall into and remain in error. In this dissenting (to the
progressive orthodoxy) theology, economics, politics and the
welfare-warfare state are not our salvation, and economists and
politicians are not our saviors. Quite the contrary: they’re false
prophets.
According to Nelson,
Knight marks the beginning of a fundamental break of the Chicago school
with the Progressives of [Paul]
Samuelson’s
ilk, a new assumption that self-interest will be expressed not only in
the marketplace but also in the actions of government and indeed perhaps
in every area of society. It’s profoundly insightful, but it’s hardly
novel: it’s simply a secularised form of an old view, characteristic of
[John]
Calvin
and other
Protestant
Reformers,
that sin has fundamentally and irredeemably … invaded every aspect
of human existence. While Roman Catholic theologians also recognised the
centrality of sin in the world, they tended to evince considerably
greater faith in human reason and in the possibilities for rational
striving toward improvement in the human condition.(11)
Not a Typical Chicagoan
Knight was a founder and leader of the Chicago School. But his means and
ends never conformed completely – or sometimes even comfortably – to
those of Friedman, Stigler and other prominent Chicagoans. He stoutly
defended market liberties; yet he also partly blamed alleged advocates
of the market – including some of his own colleagues at Chicago – for
the wholesale turn to European socialism and American progressive
principles, and resultant severe erosion of morality and liberty, that
occurred during his lifetime. In the 19th century a “religion
of liberalism had a positive social-moral content.” The 20th
century, alas, was a different story. “One of the main factors in the
present crisis,” he sagely wrote during the Great Depression, “is that
the public has lost faith, such faith as it ever had, in the moral
validity of market values.” Elsewhere he added: “the real breakdown
of bourgeois society is only superficially economic; … fundamentally,
however, [it] is … moral.” In short, classical liberalism had made a
basic “intellectual mistake” because it had “failed to see that the
social problem is not at bottom intellectual, but moral.”(12)
And in his view, no adequate moral defense of the free market could or
did emerge from his colleagues at Chicago.
|
“Knight was a founder and
leader of the Chicago School. But his means and ends never
conformed completely – or sometimes even comfortably – to
those of Friedman, Stigler and other prominent Chicagoans.” |
Knight lamented that the typical economist’s description of the market
as a “competitive” system had been “calamitous for understanding” of the
ultimate merits of a market system. Buying and selling in the market,
Knight saw, is ultimately desirable not because the resultant
competition reduces costs and prices to the lowest feasible levels. If
it were, then the case for the free market could be put in conventional
(that is, progressive and utilitarian) terms of efficiency. But it
isn’t: instead, buying and selling in the market provides the one
practical mechanism for resolving in a satisfactory way – namely one
that preserves individual freedom – the tensions among values and
preferences that accompany the development of any large and diverse
society. Knight contended that the market’s advantages should be
understood as the promotion of a “pattern of cooperation” among people
who come together on a non-coercive basis for mutual advantage. Even
people whose belief systems differ fundamentally are able, by buying and
selling in the market, to co-operate without sacrificing their diverse
values to some common set of norms. You needn’t like or otherwise
associate with Person X (be he an atheist, agnostic, lukewarm Christian,
devout Jew, etc.); but if he offers you a good or service you desire at
a price you’re happy to pay, then both benefit.
Accordingly, action in the market minimises coercive interactions.
Indeed, in a market “there are no power relations.” It enables each
person “to be the judge of his own values and of the use of his own
means to achieve them.” A Christian can trade as easily with a Muslim as
with a fellow Christian; if, however, each must first confess the same
faith, then no exchange will likely occur. Here too, Knight’s views
reflect their Christian and specifically Calvinist origins. In Christian
theology, it’s important to emphasise, private property and markets are
products of original sin. In an ideal world, neither would exist. But
ours is hardly an ideal world. In this world, property and markets
provide outlets to blunt human strivings for power and advantage. Knight
didn’t say so explicitly, but his views suggest that he rightly regarded
private property, markets and capitalism as gifts from a loving God to
his reprobate children.
Knight’s Progressive Bêtes-Noires
The theology of some of Knight’s critics – whose Christian faith,
incidentally, also underpinned their conception of economics and views
about appropriate economic policy – also help to clarify his thoughts.
Perhaps most notably, the principal founder of the American Economic
Association,
Richard
Ely,
argued early in his career (subsequently he curbed his rhetoric’s
enthusiasm, but he never tempered its thrust) that the biblical
commandment “Thou shalt love thy neighbor as thyself” rather than
self-interest should underpin social behavior. Accordingly, one could
not “serve [both] God and mammon; for the ruling motive of the one
service – egotism, selfishness – is the opposite of the ruling motive of
the other – altruism, devotion to others, consecration of heart, soul
and intellect to the service of others.” For Ely, particularly in the
Social
Gospel
phase of his life during the 1880s and 1890s, observed Nelson,
the chief motivating force in the world – even in labor and business –
must be “love” of fellow human beings, rather than the “self-interest”
long favored by most economists. Ely’s attitudes in this respect were in
fact representative of those of many leading progressive intellectuals,
often associated with the Social Gospel movement.(13)
This, Knight contended, was dangerously muddled thinking. Specifically,
in Calvinist terms it was utterly and indeed dangerously mistaken.
Specifically, it was a major instance of a general phenomenon – namely
how progressive intellectuals had substituted a fuzzy and “romantic”
conception of human nature for a clear and realistic approach. It’s
simply impossible, Knight contended, to apply “the ‘love’ doctrine” as
a guiding principle “over, say, the population of a modern nation – and,
of course, it must ultimately be over the world since, for a world
religion [like Christianity], national boundaries have no moral
significance.” Similarly, Knight rejected the economic determinism and
the resulting hope for a radical improvement in the condition of the
world (perhaps, if and when the economic problem could ever be finally
solved, attaining a state of affairs where “love” would in fact rule)
that characterised progressive theory and policy. “There is no reason,”
he contended,
to believe that if all properly economic problems were solved once [and]
for all through a fairy gift to every individual of the power to work
physical miracles, the social struggle and strife would either be
reduced in amount or intensity, or essentially changed in form, to say
nothing of improvement – in the absence of some moral revolution which
could by no means be assumed to follow in consequence of the change
itself.(14)
As Knight saw it, the core assumptions of the American progressive
gospel – namely that economic events are the driving forces in history,
and that economic progress is not just possible but, if guided by
progressive economists, inevitable – constituted an egregious misreading
of the human condition. The mere achievement of mass material
abundance cannot – either easily and quickly, or with great difficulty
over a long time – abolish the pervasive presence of sin in the world.
Indeed, material plenty can worsen spiritual poverty:
The idea that the social problem is essentially or primarily economic,
in the sense that social action may be concentrated on the economic
aspect and other aspects left to take care of themselves, is a fallacy,
and to outgrow this fallacy is one of the conditions of progress toward
a real solution of the social problem as a whole, including the economic
aspect itself. Examination will show that while many conflicts which seem
to have a non-economic character are “really” economic, it is just
as true that what is called “economic” conflict is “really” rooted in
other interests and other forms of rivalry, and that these would remain
unabated after any conceivable change in the sphere of economics alone.(15)
The Oppressive “New Religion” of Misguided Reason
Knight, remember, didn’t regard himself as a Christian. Instead, he saw
himself as a critic of Christianity and believed that in the past the
Church had often violated its creeds – and had thereby threatened man’s
liberty to act according to his conscience. In the modern age, however,
the Church was no longer the greatest threat to freedom. What was? The
new “milieu in which science as such is a religion.” This new religion –
of which economics was regrettably a significant and growing part –
promoted a “gospel” that involved “salvation by science.” This
“salvation,” moreover, reflected the old natural-law precept that
promised salvation through strict adherence to God’s laws. These
progressive follies (as Knight regarded them) were simply the latest
manifestation of a long tradition (centuries ago, priests succumbed to
it; early in the 20th century, academics followed suit) of
pandering to power and oppression in the name of reason.(16)
Bluntly, progressives had perverted science and concocted a Golden Calf.
Knight saw great danger in the increasing tendency during the 20th
century of economists to mimic and worship physical scientists. The
danger commenced in the mistaken belief that human behavior was subject
to laws and principles analogous to the laws of physical sciences. The
conviction that economists would discover more of these laws, and
thereby better explain this behaviour, increasingly accurately extended
the danger; and the ambition that they could predict and even manipulate
(“reform”) it in order to achieve the ends of their political masters
(“economic policy,” “social policy,” etc.) highlighted its invidious
consequences. This tendency, as Knight watched it harden into orthodoxy,
expressed social scientists’ unspoken – and craven – motives: “Any
attempt at use of the unqualified procedures of natural science in
solving problems of human relations,” he disclaimed, “is just another
name for a struggle for power, ultimately a completely lawless one.”
Just as the construction of a dam in order to control a river depends
upon knowledge of physical science, the advocates of the “scientific
management” of society seek to use social science as means to control
people.(17)
Given the frailty and unreliability of reason and the depravity of man’s
fallen nature, from Knight’s point of view the results of “scientific
management,” “social engineering” and the like are not merely bound to
fall well short of progressives’ expectations: their consequences,
unintended or otherwise, will be negative. Specifically, given the
self-interest of rulers and the priesthood of economists upon whose
advice they rely – the evisceration and eventual extinction of human
freedom will follow in scientific management’s wake. Progressive
economists’ grand schemes reflect their faith that the world is a
rational place. But this faith is mistaken; accordingly, “human nature
being as irrational as it is,” these schemes inevitably fail. In order
to solve social problems, according to the progressive mindset, all that
is needed “is that intellectual leaders … be converted to the scientific
point of view.” Apparently it’s really that simple: “the social problem
will be solved by the application of scientific method.”
Such thinking, Knight retorted, is mere “scientistic propaganda.” The
“fetish of scientific method” in the study of society “is one of the two
most pernicious forms of romantic folly that are current among the
educated.” Indeed, a fully rational “science of human behavior, in
the literal sense, is impossible” and a “natural or positive science of
human conduct” is “an absurdity.”(18)
A key reason is that ideas of social scientists can alter the behaviour
of the people they study. Moreover, even if a true science of society
were possible it wouldn’t be desirable.(19)
An individual whose behavior is perfectly and scientifically predictable
is not a real human being: he’s an automaton. Self-consciousness and the
ability to choose – the existence of “free will” in the Christian
formulation – distinguish people from beasts. If humans’ economic
behaviour really were as deterministic as (say) biologists conceive the
behaviour of animals, then what in moral and spiritual terms
distinguishes a man from a dog?(20)
It may well be, as Knight noted, that “the idiot” is the happiest human
being; but the mere pursuit of pleasurable sensation “is not what makes
human life worth-while”.(21)
Knight’s protest is powerful. As he readily acknowledged, however, it’s
hardly original. Four centuries earlier, and in a similar vein, Martin
Luther protested that the Roman Catholic Church had imperiled human
freedom by encouraging the faithful to believe that the good life in
this world and the attainment of salvation in the hereafter were simple
matters of rigorous and unreflective adherence to the hierarchy’s
mechanical rules. Even if there’s considerable truth to the idea that a
human being is a biological entity governed by laws of physical nature
(which surely there is), the rational methods of science can hold “no
clue to the answer to the essential problems of free society,” and the
living of lives of genuine “spiritual freedom”.(22)
The Lutheran Reformers, in opposition to the Roman Catholic orthodoxy of
their time, emphasised the scriptural truth that salvation is sola
fide (“by faith alone”) – and that faith is a gift that’s a mystery
to man and comprehensible only to God. In these regards, Knight’s
economic and broader social theology – not only its creed that original
sin undermines any human effort to act rationally, and indeed underpins
some of man’s most evil actions – broadly reflects protestant theology.
Martin Luther often invoked St Paul’s message that “the flesh lusteth
against the spirit and the spirit contrary to the flesh” and therefore
“so that ye cannot do the things that ye would do.”(23)
Like the Protestant Reformers, Knight doubted the benefits of human
“works.” He rejected the optimistic faith that the scientific management
of society (the secular counterpart of “works”) is the path to the
eventual perfection – or even great improvement – of human existence.
Contrary to the rationalist theology of Thomas Aquinas and the
mechanical prescriptions of contemporary economics, no mere set of rules
can ever show the way to heaven – here on earth or otherwise. For this
reason, Ross Emmett concluded that Knight’s thinking constitutes an
essentially theological view of the basic economic choices facing any
society:
In a society which has no recourse to the providential nature of a God
who is present in human history, the provision of a justification for the way society works is a “theological” undertaking. Despite the fact that
modern economists often forget it, their investigations of the universal
problem of scarcity and its consequences for human behavior and social
organization is a form of theological inquiry: in a world where there is
no God, scarcity replaces moral evil as the central problem of theodicy,
and the process of assigning value becomes the central problem
of morality. Knight’s (implicit) recognition of the theological nature
of economic inquiry in this regard is one of the reasons for his
rejection of positivism in economics and his insistence on the
fundamentally normative and apologetic character of economics.
In some sense, therefore, it is appropriate to say that Knight
understood that his role in a society which did not or could
not recognize the presence of God was similar to the role of a
theologian in a society which explicitly acknowledged God’s presence. As
a student of society, he was obliged to contribute to society’s
discussion of the appropriate mechanisms for the coordination of
individuals’ actions, and to remind the members of society that their
discussion could never be divorced from consideration of the type of
society they wanted to create and the kind of people they wanted to
become.(24)
|
1. See Ross B. Emmett's overview of Knight's thinking in
The Elgar Companion to The Chicago School of Economics, Elgar, 2010, p. 238.
2. Risk, Uncertainty and Profit describes and explains Knight's
conception of the entrepreneur's role in economy and society. It's best-known
for its distinction between economic risk and uncertainty. The outcomes
of "risky" situations (such as the toss of a fair coin) are unknown but
nonetheless governed by "known" (that is, plausibly assumed)
mathematical-statistical models called probability distributions. Knight
contended that these situations, where concrete rules (such as the
maximisation of expected utility) can be applied and accurate and
reliable probabilities can be computed, differ fundamentally from "uncertain"
situations (such as the survival and growth of a new enterprise). In
these latter situations, not only the outcomes but also the probability
distributions that generate them are unknown. Uncertainty, Knight argued,
presents to entrepreneurs the opportunity to generate economic profits
that perfect competition (in the sense that economists normally
understand the term) cannot eliminate.
3. Razeen Sally, "The Political Economy of Frank Knight: Classical
Liberalism from Chicago," Constitutional Political Economy, vol. 8, no.
2, 1997, pp 123-138 and Ross B. Emmett, "Frank Knight: Economics versus
Religion," in H. Geoffrey Brennan and A. M. C. Waterman, eds., Economics
and Religion: Are They Distinct? Kluwer, 1994, pp. 118-119.
4. Essays
on and in the Chicago Tradition, Duke University Press, 1980, p. 46.
5. See in particular William S. Kern, "Frank Knight on Preachers and
Economic Policy: A Nineteenth Century Anti-Religionist, He Thought
Religion Should Support the Status Quo," American Journal of Economics
and Sociology, vol. 47, no. 1 (January 1988), pp. 61-69.
6. The First Unitarian Church of Chicago is a Unitarian Universalist ("UU")
church. Unitarians share no common creed and include people who confess
a wide variety of personal beliefs - including deists, pantheists,
polytheists, pagans, agnostics and others. See James Ishmael Ford, Zen
Master Who? Wisdom Publications, 2006, p. 187. See also James M.
Buchanan, "The Economizing Element in Knight's Ethical Critique of
Capitalist Order," Ethics, vol. 98 (October 1987) pp. 246, 247.
7. See in particular Knight's article "Ethics and Economic Reform:
Christianity" in Economica, vol. 6, November 1939, pp. 398-422.
8. "Frank Knight's Pluralism," Critical Review, vol. 11, Fall 1997, pp.
537-554.
9. See in particular Knight, "Pragmatism and Social Action,"
International Journal of Ethics, vol. 46, no. 2 (January 1936), pp.
229-236.
10. Private Property: The History of an Idea, Russell and Russell,
Rutgers University Press, 1951, p. 35.
11. Economics as Religion: from Samuelson to Chicago and Beyond, p.
120.
12. Knight, "Social Science and the Political Trend,"
University of
Toronto Quarterly, vol. 3, 1934, pp. 280-287 and Knight, "Ethics and
Economic Reform: The Ethics of Liberalism," Economica, vol. 6, no. 21 (February
1939), pp. 1-29.
13. See also Frank H. Knight and Charles Howard Hopkins,
The Rise of
the Social Gospel in American Protestantism, 1865-1915, Yale University
Press, 1940.
14. "Ethics and Economic Reform," p. 408.
15. "Ethics and Economic Reform," p. 410.
16. Knight, "Pragmatism and Social Action," p. 53; Knight,
"Salvation by Science: The Gospel According to Professor Lundberg," Journal
of Political Economy, vol. 55 (December 1947), pp. 537-52; and Daniel J.
Hammond, "Frank Knight's Anti-positivism," History of Political Economy,
vol. 23, no. 3 (Fall, 1991), pp. 359-381.
17. Knight, "The Limitations of Scientific Method in Economics," in
The
Trend of Economics, ed. Rexford Tugwell, New York: Alfred A. Knopf, pp.
229-67; Knight, "Free Society: Its Basic Nature and Problem,"
Philosophical Review, vol. 57, no. 1 (January 1948), pp. 39-58; and
Richard A. Gonce, "Frank H. Knight on Social Control and the Scope and
Method of Economics," Southern Economic Journal, vol. 38, no. 4 (April
1972), pp. 547-558.
18. Knight, "Abstract Economics as Absolute Ethics,"
Ethics, vol. 76,
no. 3 (April 1966), pp. 163-177 and Knight, "Salvation by Science: The
Gospel According to Professor Lundberg," Journal of Political Economy,
vol. 55, no. 6 (December 1947), pp. 229-230, 235.
19. Knight, "The Role of Principles in Economics and Politics," pp.
261, 258, 260, and Knight, "Economic Psychology and the Value Problem,"
Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. 39, no. 2 (May 1925), pp. 372-409.
20. Among contemporary economists, one ?nds the clearest echo of
Knight's thinking in the writings of his former student James Buchanan.
Indeed, on many subjects Buchanan sounds remarkably similar to Knight.
For example, Buchanan considers that a person who behaves strictly
according to scienti? c laws "could not be concerned with choice at
all." Indeed, it is "internally contradictory" to speak of individual "choice
making under [scienti? c] certainty." If human dignity and freedom
require the power to choose, and if the ability to do either good or
evil must be within the scope of individual decision making, then,
Buchanan believes, scientific rules cannot determine human behaviour.
Indeed, "the scienti? c view of a human being as mechanical instrument
denies a person his or her basic humanity." See James M. Buchanan,
What
Should Economists Do? (Liberty Press, 1979), p. 281.
21. See Knight, "The Role of Principles in Economics and Politics,"
American Economic Review, vol. 41, March 1951, p. 279.
22. Knight, "The Free Society: Its Basic Nature and Problem,"
Philosophical Review, vol. 57, no. 1, 1948, pp. 39-41.
23. John Kohl, "Christianity: Protestantism," in R. C. Zaehner,
Encyclopedia of the World's Religions, Barnes and Noble, 1997, p. 101.
24. Ross B. Emmett, "Frank Knight: Economics versus Religion," in H.
Geoffrey Brennan and A. M. C. Waterman, eds., Economics and Religion:
Are They Distinct? Kluwer, 1994, pp. 118-19. |
|
From the same author |
▪
Austerity, What Austerity? Europe Desperately Needs
"Genuine Austerity"
(no
317 – December 15, 2013)
▪
The shameful treatment of Ron Paul by the mainstream
media
(no
300 – May 15, 2012)
▪
The Evil Princes of Martin
Place – Introduction
(no
286 – February 15, 2011)
▪
The return of Keynesianism
(no
278 – May 15, 2010)
▪
Why do we have recurrent economic booms and busts?
(no
262 – December 15, 2008)
▪
More...
|
|
First written appearance of the
word 'liberty,' circa 2300 B.C. |
Le Québécois Libre
Promoting individual liberty, free markets and voluntary
cooperation since 1998.
|
|