THE RATIONAL ARGUMENTATOR |
Universal Physical and Moral Laws, With No Lawgiver |
Here I endeavor to refute the
common argument that any law, be it a physical law or a law
of morality or justice, requires a lawgiver – an intelligent
entity that brought the law into being. While some laws (termed
manmade or positive laws) do indeed have human lawmakers, a
much more fundamental class of laws (termed universal or
natural laws) arise not due to promulgation by any
intelligent being, but rather due to the basic properties of
the entities these laws concern, and the relations of those
entities to one another. To the extent that positive laws
are enacted by humans, the purpose of such positive laws
should be reflect and effectuate the beneficial consequences
of objectively valid natural laws. For instance, it is a
natural law that each human being possesses a right to life.
A positive law that prohibits and punishes murder of one
human being by another would reflect the natural law and
therefore be desirable. On the other hand, if any positive
law were to mandate murder (as various edicts by
tyrannical regimes throughout history, targeting political
dissidents or disfavored minority groups, have done), then
that positive law would be contrary to the natural law and
therefore illegitimate and harmful.
The physical laws of nature
pertain to all entities, including humans, and describe the
regularities with which these entities will behave within
applicable situations. Examples of physical laws include
Newton’s Three Laws of Motion, the law of gravitation, the
law of conservation of matter and energy, and the law of
conservation of momentum. If it is asserted that these laws
require a lawgiver, then the lawgiver would hypothetically
be able to alter these laws on a whim at any time, thereby
depriving them of their universality and predictable
application. Such a state of affairs would not only be
highly inconvenient (to say the least), but also completely
incompatible with the reality that these laws are
derived from the nature of entities as they are.
We can draw upon ubiquitous
observation and the fact that these laws of nature can
indeed be harnessed so precisely that every functional
technology ever invented works because it takes advantage of
them. The argument that the laws of nature could change
tomorrow depends on a false perception of what those laws
are – a kind of Platonic view that the laws of nature are
superimposed upon the world of objects. In reality, however,
objects (entities) and their qualities and relationships are
all that exist at the most basic level. The laws of nature
are relationships that are derived from the very properties
inherent to objects themselves; they are not some higher
layer of reality on top of the objects that leads the
objects to behave in a certain way. That is, the laws of
nature are what they are because the things whose behavior
they describe are what they are.
The truth that the laws of
nature are a function of the objects whose behavior they
describe pertains to fundamental physical laws, such as the
law of gravitation. While the law of gravitation and the
equation(1) describing that law apply universally, the very
existence of the law is dependent on the existence of
entities that have mass and therefore exhibit gravitational
attraction. Were there no entities or no entities with mass
(incidentally, both logically impossible scenarios), then
the concept of gravity would not have any relevance or
applicability. Likewise, the amount of mass of particular
entities and their distance of separation from one another
will determine the extent of the gravitational force exerted
by those entities upon one another. The gravitational force
arises because the entities are as massive as they are and
located where they are relative to one another; it does not
arise because a supernatural lawgiver imposed it upon
entities who would otherwise be completely static or random
in their behavior in relation to one another.
The key parallel with the laws
of morality is that, as the laws of gravitation stem from
the objective properties of entities themselves (i.e., that
they have mass – which is a universal property of all
entities), so do the laws of morality stem from the
objective properties of human beings themselves – namely,
the biological and physical prerequisites of human survival
and flourishing. Different specific decisions may be the
appropriate moral decisions in different contexts, but
because of the essential similarities of humans along many
key dimensions, certain general moral truths will hold
universally for all humans. But again, were there no humans
(or similar rational, sentient, volitional beings) with
these essential attributes, the concept of morality would
have no relevance.
|
“Neither morality nor
gravitation require the existence of entities outside of
those exhibiting moral behavior or gravitational attraction.
A system of physical or moral laws is not dependent on an
outside ‘lawgiver’
but rather on the objective natures of the entities
partaking in the system.” |
Neither morality nor
gravitation require the existence of entities outside of
those exhibiting moral behavior or gravitational attraction.
A system of physical or moral laws is not dependent on an
outside “lawgiver” but rather on the objective natures of
the entities partaking in the system. Objective moral laws
include the principles of ethics, which address how a person
should behave to maximize possible well-being, as well as
the principles of justice, which address how people should
relate to one another in respecting one another’s spheres of
legitimate action, rewarding meritorious conduct, and
punishing destructive conduct against others. There is a
natural harmony between adherence to objective moral laws
and the attainment of beneficial consequences for one’s own
life, material prosperity, and happiness – provided that one
adheres to a view of long-term, enlightened, rational self-interest,
which does not allow one to sacrifice the lives, liberty, or
property of others to achieve a short-term gain.
Some would assert that
principles of behavior that tend to maximize well-being and
serve one’s rational self-interest may be part of prudent or
practical conduct, but are not the same as morality. In the
minds of these individuals, morality (typically, in their
view, willed by an external lawgiver) is independent of
practical means or consequences and often (as, for instance,
in Immanuel Kant’s outlook on morality) inherently divorced
from actions conducive to self-interest. I, however,
strongly reject any notion that there might be a dichotomy
between morality and practicality, happiness, or prosperity
– when a long-term, enlightened, and multifaceted outlook on
the latter conditions is considered. Some might be so short-sighted
as to mistake some temporary advantage or fleeting pleasure
for true fulfillment or happiness, but the objective
cause-and-effect relationships within our physical reality
will eventually disappoint them (if they live long enough –
and if not, their punishment – death – will be even greater).
If some or even many humans might be drawn toward certain
pleasurable feelings for their own sake (which is an
evolutionary relic of a very different primeval environment
inhabited by our ancestors – but a tendency ill-adapted to
our current environment), this is not the same as achieving
truly sustainable prosperity and happiness by using reason
to thrive in our current environment (or to create a better
environment for human flourishing). One of the objectives of
a good moral system is to guide people toward the latter
outcome. My
essay and
video “Commonly Misunderstood Concepts: Happiness” offer
more detailed thoughts on key elements of a life of
flourishing and the concept of eudaemonia – the
actualization of one’s full potential, as Aristotle and
later virtue-oriented philosophers described of it.
Objective moral law, derived
from the fundamental value of every innocent rational,
sentient being’s life, posits an essential harmony of the
long-term, enlightened self-interests of all who earnestly
pursue truth and goodness. Unlike many proponents of an
externally legislated moral framework (for which
the alleged lawgiver might be a supernatural being, a single
human ruler, or a collective of humans), I would not
consider self-sacrifice to be a component of morality. I
align more with Ayn Rand’s view of sacrifice as a surrender
of a greater value (e.g., one’s life) to a lesser value (e.g.,
abstractions such as nation-states, religions, or perceived
slights from another nation-state or religious or cultural
group). A person can behave morally – promoting his own
life, respecting the rights of others, and contributing to
human flourishing – without ever surrendering anything he
values (except as an instrument for obtaining outcomes he
might justifiably value more). Morality should therefore
not be seen as the subordination of the individual to
some higher ideal, be it a divine order or a manmade one.
Rather, the individual is the ideal for which moral
behavior is the path to fulfillment.
A person who behaves morally
advances himself while fully respecting the legitimate
prerogatives of others. He improves his own life without
damaging anybody else’s. In the process of pursuing
enlightened self-interest, he also benefits the lives of
others through value-adding interactions. Indeed, he may
enter into an extensive network of both formal and informal
reciprocal obligations with others that result in his
actions being a constant, sustainable source of improvement
in others’ lives. The virtue of honesty is part of objective
ethics and impels a moral individual to strive to honor all
commitments once they have been made. The key to a morality
based on objective, natural law, however, is that these
obligations be entered into freely and not as a result of
the self being compromised in favor of an alleged higher
ideal. Consequently, a key component of natural law is the
liberty of an individual to evaluate the world in accordance
with his rational faculty and to decide which undertakings
are consistent with his enlightened self-interest. When
positive laws are crafted so as to interfere with that
liberty, positive law becomes at odds with natural law,
leading to warped incentives, institutionalized sacrifices,
and painful tradeoffs that many individuals must make if
they seek to abide by both natural and positive laws.
Objective natural laws – both
physical and moral – do not require a lawgiver and antecede
manmade, positive laws. Some natural laws, however, may
require positive laws – such as prohibitions on murder,
theft, and slavery – in order for the desirable outcome
brought about by the natural laws to be reflected in actual
(rather than simply hoped-for) human behavior. In order to
improve human well-being, positive laws should be developed
to advance and effectuate natural laws, instead of
attempting to resist them or contravene them. Just as a law
that redefines the value of pi as 3.2 (one actually
unsuccessfully attempted in Indiana in 1897) is rightly
seen as absurd on its face, even if a majority votes to
enact it, and would result in many failed constructions if
implemented by engineers and designers of machines, so would
a law that abrogates the natural liberty of individuals to
peacefully pursue their own flourishing result in damage to
good human beings and increases in physical harm, suffering,
and injustice. A good human lawmaker should respect
pre-existing objective natural laws and not attempt to
contradict them.
|
1. F = G*m1*m2/r2,
with F being the force between two masses, m1 and
m2 being the two masses, r being the distance
between the centers of the two masses, and G being the
universal gravitational constant. |
|
From the same author |
▪
The Ukrainian Regime's Censorship Spreads West to
Canada, and Political Correctness is to Blame
(no
331 – April 15, 2015)
▪
Review of Robert Wilfred Franson's The Shadow of
the Ship
(no
330 – March 15, 2015)
▪
To Prevent World War III, Do Not Arm Ukraine's Regime
(no
329 – February 15, 2015)
▪
We Must Proudly Reassert Free Speech and Universal
Western Values
(no
328 – January 15, 2015)
▪
Henry Hazlitt's Time Will Run Back: Unleashing
Business to Improve the Human Condition
(no
327 – December 15, 2014)
▪
More...
|
|
First written appearance of the
word 'liberty,' circa 2300 B.C. |
Le Québécois Libre
Promoting individual liberty, free markets and voluntary
cooperation since 1998.
|
|