THE RATIONAL ARGUMENTATOR |
Fast-Track Atheist Security Lanes and More: Time to Jettison
Perverse Egalitarianism |
I agree fully with the
recent recommendation by journalist, author, and US
Transhumanist Party presidential candidate Zoltan Istvan to establish fast-track security lanes in airports, enabling
declared atheists to avoid wasteful, humiliating, and time-consuming
security procedures ostensibly designed to ferret out potential
terrorists. The rationale behind Istvan’s recommendation is
straightforward: since the motivation for virtually every plane
hijacking has been some manner of religious fundamentalism, it
is time to recognize that the probability of an atheist
perpetrating such a terrible act is negligible and spare
atheists the stigma and inconvenience of invasive screenings.
Indeed, even the argument of certain religious critics of
atheism that “there are no atheists in foxholes” can be used to
bolster Istvan’s proposal. If it is indeed the case that a lack
of a belief in a deity or an afterlife leads to a greater
reluctance to risk one’s own life in battle for some ostensibly
“higher” ideal, then this could be expected to translate to an
even greater reluctance to perpetrate plane hijackings, suicide
bombings, or other self-sacrificial atrocities, which lack even
the blessing that political authorities bestow upon organized
warfare.
Of course, it is also the case that most religious
people would never perpetrate acts of terrorism, and it would be
desirable to include in Istvan’s fast-track process any
particular types of religious adherents for whom the
perpetration of wanton murder for ideological objectives would
be similarly inconceivable. Jainism, for instance, upholds
nonviolence toward all living beings, as do some interpretations
of Buddhism. Various Christian denominations throughout history
– Quakers, Mennonites, and certain Anglicans – have been
pacifistic as well. In addition to anyone who professes these
beliefs, all people who can demonstrate that they are opposed to
war and political violence in general should be exempted from
airport screenings as well.
But we can, and should, be even more expansive in determining
eligibility for fast-track security lanes. For instance, the
probability of a two-year-old toddler, a 70-year-old grandmother,
or a visibly afflicted cancer patient seeking to perpetrate an
act of terrorism is just as negligible as that of an atheist or
a pacifist. Screening people of those demographics – and many
others – is equally pointless. It is similarly inconceivable
that people with high-profile public lives – celebrities,
businesspeople, holders of political office – would perpetrate
plane hijackings, and yet the current airport “security”
procedures apply to them all. One could, with some deliberation,
arrive at tens of other attributes that would preclude their
possessors from being terrorist threats. In progressively
filtering out more and more people as having virtually no
probability of committing mass attacks on civilians, it would be
possible to rapidly restore liberty and convenience to virtually
all airline passengers. Furthermore, this more expansive
clearance from suspicion should apply not just with regard to
airport screenings, but also with regard to any
surveillance of a person’s activities. The logical end result
would be to roll back both “security” screenings by the
Transportation Security Administration (TSA) and mass
surveillance by the National Security Agency (NSA) until each of
these processes is focused solely on perhaps a few hundred
genuine suspects while leaving the rest of us alone to live and
travel in peace. Or, perhaps better yet, we should start with
the age-old presumption of free societies: that an individual is
deemed innocent unless he or she has shown evidence of guilt.
So, instead of developing an array of characteristics that would
enable people to opt out of detailed scrutiny, the
system should be designed to only surveil an individual if there
is probable cause and a strong reason to suspect criminal intent
on the part of that specific individual. In short, we would
return to the libertarian and classical liberal approach to
issues of security.
Even if the detection and thwarting of terrorists were one’s
sole goal, it would be logical to support as many valid
methods as possible for narrowing the scope of one’s focus
toward those who might pose genuine threats. The less time and
effort are spent screening and surveilling completely innocent
people, the more resources can be directed toward pursuing and
thwarting actual wrongdoers.
And yet nobody seeking to fly today is safe from intrusive
scrutiny, and the political class will take neither Istvan’s
more limited recommendation nor my more expansive one seriously.
Why is it that, in contemporary America, whenever somebody does
something sufficiently terrible to generate headlines,
procedures are deployed to ensnare everybody in a web
of ceaseless suspicion, humiliation, and moral outrage? When a
handful of fanatics hijack planes, destroy buildings, and murder
civilians, the vast majority of civilians, who resemble the
victims far more than the perpetrators, nonetheless become
the principal targets of spying, prying, groping, and
expropriation. Some libertarians will make the argument, not to
be discounted, that the genuine purpose of the mass surveillance
and screenings is not to catch terrorists, but rather
to instill submissive attitudes in the general population,
rendering more pliable those who have been acculturated to
inconvenience for inconvenience’s sake, just because those in
authority ordered it. Yet such a nefarious motive could not be
the sole sustaining force behind persistent mass surveillance
and humiliation, as most people do not have an interest in
subjugation for the sake of subjugation, and enough people of
good conscience would eventually unite against it and overturn
its exercise. Another mindset, which I will call perverse
egalitarianism, unfortunately afflicts even many people of
generally good intentions. It is the prevalence of this perverse
egalitarianism that enables the perpetration of mass outrages to
persist.
|
“When a handful of fanatics
hijack planes, destroy buildings, and murder civilians, the
vast majority of civilians, who resemble the victims
far more than the perpetrators, nonetheless become the
principal targets of spying, prying, groping, and
expropriation.” |
Perverse egalitarianism, essentially, upholds the
equality of outcomes above the nature of those
outcomes. To a perverse egalitarian, it is more important to
prevent some people from receiving more favorable treatments,
resources, or prerogatives than others, than it is to expand the
total scope of opportunities available for improving people’s
lives. The perverse egalitarian mindset holds that, unless
everybody is able to get something favorable, nobody should have
it.
For those who value “equality” – however defined – there are
two essential ways to achieve it – one, by uplifting those who
are less well-off so that they are able to enjoy what those who
are better off already enjoy; the other, by depriving those who
are currently better off of their advantages and prerogatives.
From a moral standpoint, these two types of egalitarianism
cannot be farther apart; the first seeks to improve the lives of
some, whereas the second seeks to degrade the lives of others.
The first type of egalitarianism – the uplifting form – is
admirable in its desire to improve lives, but also more
difficult to realize. Beneficial qualities in life do not
magically appear but often require the generation of real wealth
from previously unavailable sources. Through technological and
economic progress, the uplifting form of egalitarianism has a
potential to succeed, although, paradoxically, it can best
emerge by tolerating the natural inequalities associated with a
market economy. Free enterprise will generate tremendous wealth
for some, which in turn will enable vast numbers of others to
achieve more modest prosperity and emerge out of dire poverty.
The most economically and societally unequal societies are the
most authoritarian and primitive, in which an entrenched caste
of rulers controls virtually all the advantages and resources,
while the rest of the population lives in squalor. Often, those
are the very same societies that embrace “leveling” and
redistributive policies in the name of achieving equality. As
Milton and Rose Friedman
famously wrote in
Free to Choose, “A society that puts equality – in the
sense of equality of outcome – ahead of freedom will end up with
neither equality nor freedom. The use of force to achieve
equality will destroy freedom, and the force, introduced for
good purposes, will end up in the hands of people who use it to
promote their own interests. On the other hand, a society that
puts freedom first will, as a happy by-product, end up with both
greater freedom and greater equality.”
But perverse egalitarianism is much easier to implement than
uplifting egalitarianism. Indeed, it is much easier to destroy
than to create. The perverse egalitarian does not even need to
do anything to improve the lot of the worse-off; he or she just
needs to bring the better-off down to their level. But the
greatest taboo for the perverse egalitarian is to allow anybody,
for whatever reason, to escape the “leveling” process and “get
away with” an advantage that another lacks. Perverse
egalitarianism is the reason why “security” measures ostensibly
designed to catch a handful of wrongdoers and prevent potential
attacks by a tiny minority of perpetrators, almost inevitably
burden the entire population. It would be “unfair”, according to
the perverse egalitarians, to scrutinize only a subset of
people, while letting others walk into airplanes unsearched or
live their lives un-surveilled. Because it is indeed true that
some people cannot altogether escape suspicion, the perverse
egalitarians believe that nobody should be able to. To do
otherwise would be to commit the cardinal sin of “profiling” –
never mind that the perverse egalitarians’ way would visit the
very same inconveniences of such profiling upon everybody.
But perverse egalitarianism brings only the permanent
enshrinement of suffering under the guise of equality or “social
justice”. It is reprehensible to make everyone suffer simply
because an inconvenience might justifiably exist for some. And
while profiling on the basis of circumstantial attributes is
itself morally and practically questionable, there is no
question that, from a purely probabilistic standpoint, certain
attributes can rule out suspicion far more definitively than
others. As an example, while the risk that an atheist would
hijack an airplane is negligible, it is incontrovertible that
some fundamentalist Muslims have hijacked airplanes in the past.
It is still true that even most fundamentalist Muslims would
never hijack airplanes, but just knowing that someone is a
fundamentalist Muslim would not tell us this; we would need to
know more about that individual’s outlook. But, in spite of all
this, it is eminently reasonable to spare the atheist any
further scrutiny; the only purported argument for not
doing this would be to avoid “offending” the fundamentalist
Muslim or creating an appearance of unequal treatment. But this
is precisely the perverse egalitarian position – affirmatively
inflicting real suffering on some in order to avoid perceived
slights on the part of others. The best approach is to seek to
treat everyone justly, not to spread injustice as widely and
“equally” as possible. Highly targeted approaches toward threat
detection should be used to focus solely on probable offenders
while deliberately aiming to keep as many people as possible out
of the scope of searches and surveillance.
Zoltan Istvan’s proposal to spare atheists from intrusive
airport screenings would be a step forward compared to the
status quo, but his argument, taken to its logical
conclusion, should lead to virtually everybody being
“fast-tracked” through airport security. The special treatment,
and special lines, should be reserved for the tiny minority of
likely wrongdoers who truly warrant suspicion.
|
|
From the same author |
▪
Universal Physical and Moral Laws, With No Lawgiver
(no
332 – May 15, 2015)
▪
The Ukrainian Regime's Censorship Spreads West to
Canada, and Political Correctness is to Blame
(no
331 – April 15, 2015)
▪
Review of Robert Wilfred Franson's The Shadow of
the Ship
(no
330 – March 15, 2015)
▪
To Prevent World War III, Do Not Arm Ukraine's Regime
(no
329 – February 15, 2015)
▪
We Must Proudly Reassert Free Speech and Universal
Western Values
(no
328 – January 15, 2015)
▪
More...
|
|
First written appearance of the
word 'liberty,' circa 2300 B.C. |
Le Québécois Libre
Promoting individual liberty, free markets and voluntary
cooperation since 1998.
|
|