THE RATIONAL ARGUMENTATOR |
Refuting Ayn Rand's 'Immortal Robot' Argument |
Here I refute an argument that
has been leveled against proponents of indefinite human
longevity from a surprising direction – those sympathetic to
the Objectivist philosophy of Ayn Rand. Some advocates of
Ayn Rand’s philosophy believe that indefinite life would
turn human beings into “immortal, indestructible robots”
that, according to Ayn Rand, would have no genuine values.
Both of these claims are false. Indefinite life would not
turn humans into indestructible robots, nor would an
indestructible robot with human abilities lack values or
motivation for doing great things. In Ayn Rand’s own words,
“Achieving life is not the equivalent of avoiding death.”
(John Galt’s speech in For the New Intellectual, p.
135)
Rand’s “immortal robot”
argument is found in “The Objectivist Ethics” (The
Virtue of Selfishness, p. 15): “To make this point
fully clear, try to imagine an immortal, indestructible
robot, an entity which moves and acts, but which cannot be
affected by anything, which cannot be changed in any
respect, which cannot be damaged, injured or destroyed. Such
an entity would not be able to have any values; it would
have nothing to gain or to lose; it could not regard
anything as for or against it, as serving
or threatening its welfare, as fulfilling or frustrating its
interests. It could have no interests and no goals.”
The “immortal robot” argument
needs to be challenged because it originates from Ayn Rand,
who otherwise espouses numerous rational ideas. I myself
agree with most of the fundamental principles that Ayn Rand
advocates. However, in some of her particular reasoning – at
least, if applied to the wrong context – she can be off-target
in such a way as to retard further progress. The often-leveled
argument, derived by contemporary non-transhumanist
Objectivists from the above-quoted passage, is that
achieving indefinite longevity would turn human beings into
Ayn Rand’s description of the “immortal, indestructible
robot.”
In responding to Rand’s
argument, several points can be made in relation to
prolonging human life indefinitely and lifting the death
sentence that hangs over all of us. First, at no point in
time will human beings become the “immortal, indestructible
robots” that Ayn Rand describes. The simple reason for this
is that our existence is physical and contingent on certain
physical prerequisites being fulfilled. The moment one of
these physical prerequisites is lacking, our existence
ceases. This will always be the case, even if we no longer
have a necessary upper limit on our lifespans. For instance,
biomedical advances that would greatly expand human
lifespans – allowing periodic reversions to a more youthful
biological state and therefore the possibility of an
indefinite existence – would not turn humans into
indestructible robots. There would still be the need to
actively turn back biological processes of decay, and the
active choice to pursue such treatments or not. People who
live longer by successfully combating senescence could still
get run over by a car or experience a plane crash. They
would retain potential vulnerability to certain perils –
such as death from accidents – although, as I have explained
in “Life
Extension and Risk Aversion,” they may be more diligent
in seeking to greatly reduce the probability of such
outcomes. If it is ever the case that death by senescence
and the myriad diseases which kill many human beings today
can be averted, then human beings will try to avert the
other possibilities of death – for instance, by developing
safer modes of transportation or engaging in fewer wars.
It is possible to significantly
reduce the likelihood that one can be destroyed, without
ever eliminating the theoretical potential of such
destruction. Furthermore, because human beings have free
will, they always have at least the hypothetical option of
choosing to undermine the physical prerequisites of their
own lives. In my view, no sane, rational being would
actually choose to pursue that option, but the option is
there nonetheless. For anybody who seeks to commit suicide
by immediate or gradual means, or by refusing to take
advantage of life-prolonging techniques once they become
available, there is virtually nothing in the world that
could prevent this, apart from rational persuasion (which
may or may not be successful).
Even with indefinite longevity,
human beings will always be vulnerable to some actual or
hypothetical perils or poor choices. Moreover, when we
manage to avoid one kind of peril, other kinds of perils may
become more pressing as they come into the frame of
awareness of longer-lived beings. If we do manage to live
for hundreds of thousands of years, we will be far more
subject to long-term geological changes and fluctuations of
the Earth’s climate, such as the
cycle of ice ages, whereas today humans do not live long
enough to experience these massive shifts. Most of us today
do not worry about the consequences of huge glaciers
advancing over the continents, but humans who live for
millennia will see this as a pressing problem for their own
lifetimes. Likewise, the longer we live, the greater the
likelihood that we will experience a global cataclysm, such
as a supervolcano or an asteroid hitting the Earth. Human
ingenuity and resources would need to be devoted toward
confronting and even preventing these perils – a highly
desirable outcome in general, since the perils exist
irrespective of our individual lifespans, but most humans
currently lack the long-term vision or orientation to combat
them.
Moreover, the need to reject
the “immortal robot” argument when discussing indefinite
life extension does not stem solely from a desire to achieve
philosophical correctness. Rather, we should recognize the
potential for actually achieving meaningful, unprecedented
longevity increases within our own lifetimes. For instance,
the SENS
Research Foundation is a nonprofit biogerontological
research organization whose founder, Dr. Aubrey de Grey, has
outlined an engineering-based approach to reversing the
seven principal types of damage that accumulate in the human
body with age. (SENS stands for “Strategies for Engineered
Negligible Senescence.”) Dr. de Grey has stated that, with
proper funding, there is approximately a 50 percent
probability of these rejuvenation treatments being developed
20-25 years from now. (The 20-year figure is presented in
this transcript from a recent NPR interview of Aubrey de
Grey – quoted in “Discussing
Science and Aging: Aubrey de Grey and Cynthia Kenyon at NPR”
by Reason at FightAging.org.) The SENS Research Foundation
is not the only entity pursuing radical life extension.
Major commercial efforts toward research into reversing
biological aging – such as Calico, created and funded by
Google (now Alphabet, Inc.) – have been launched already.
Thus, it is premature to conclude that death is a certainty
for those who are alive today. Medical advances on the
horizon could indeed turn many humans into beings who are
still potentially vulnerable to death, but no longer subject
to any upper limit on their lifespans.
|
“It is ill-advised to
pin any ethical justifications for the ultimate value of
human life to the current contingent situation, where it
just so happens that human lifespans are finite because we
have not achieved the level of technological advancement to
overcome senescence yet.” |
It is therefore ill-advised to
pin any ethical justifications for the ultimate value of
human life to the current contingent situation, where it
just so happens that human lifespans are finite because we
have not achieved the level of technological advancement to
overcome senescence yet. If such advances are achieved,
common interpretations of the “immortal robot” argument and
its derivative claims would suggest that life for human
beings would transform from an ultimate value to some lesser
value or to no value at all. This implication reveals a flaw
in arguments that rely on the finitude of life and the
inevitability of death. How is it that, by making life
longer, healthier, and of higher quality (with less
suffering due to the diseases of old age), humans would, in
so doing, deprive life of its status as an ultimate value?
If life is improved, it does not thereby lose a moral status
that it previously possessed.
Yet another important
recognition is that some animals have already attained
negligible senescence. Their lifespans are de facto
finite, but without a necessary upper limit. Suppose
that evolution had taken a different course and rational
beings had descended from tortoises rather than from
primates. Then these rational beings would have negligible
senescence without the need for medical intervention to
achieve it. Would their lives thereby lack a type of value
which the proponents of the “immortal robot” argument
attribute to human lives today? Again, a conclusion of this
sort illustrates a flaw in the underlying argument.
But suppose that a true
immortal, indestructible robot could exist and be identical
to human beings in every other respect. It would possess
human biological processes and ways of thinking but be made
of extremely strong materials that did not deteriorate or
that automatically renewed themselves so as to rapidly,
automatically repair any injury. Ayn Rand’s argument would
still be mistaken. Even if death were not a possibility for
such a being, it could still pursue and enjoy art, music,
inventions, games – any activity that is appealing from the
perspective of the senses, the intellect, or the general
civilizing project of transforming chaos into order and
transforming simpler orders into more complex ones.
The fear of death is not the
sole motivator for human actions by far. Indeed, most great
human accomplishments are a result of positive, not negative
motivations. Rand acknowledged this when she wrote that
“Achieving life is not the equivalent of avoiding death.” At
least in the short term, you do not need to do much to avoid
death. You could just sit there, stay out of trouble, eat,
drink, keep warm, sleep – and you survive to the next day.
But that is not a full life, according to Rand. Obviously,
one needs to avoid death to have a full life. Survival is
necessary, but it is not sufficient. Many thinkers
sympathetic to the Objectivist school, such as Edward
Younkins, Tara Smith, Douglas Den Uyl, Douglas Rasmussen,
Tibor Machan, George Reisman, and Lester Hunt, have extended
this insight to conclude that survival is not enough; one
should also pursue flourishing. (Younkins provides
an excellent overview of this perspective in “Flourishing
and Happiness in a Nutshell.”)
I concur fully with the goal of
flourishing and recognize the existence of numerous positive
motivations besides mere survival. For example, the desire
to see oneself create something, to witness a product of
one’s mind become embodied in the physical reality, is a
powerful motivation indeed. One can furthermore seek to take
esthetic pleasure from a particular object or activity. This
does not require even a thought of death. Moreover, to
appreciate certain kinds of patterns in existence, which are
present in art, in technology, and even in games, does not
require any thought of death. Many people play games, even
if those games do not contribute anything to their survival.
This does not mean, however, that doing so is irrational;
rather, it is another creative way to channel the activities
of the human mind. Via games, the human mind essentially
creates its own field of endeavor, a rule system within
which it operates. By operating within that rule system, the
mind exercises its full potential, whereas just by sitting
there and only doing what is absolutely necessary to
survive, the mind would have missed some essential part of
its functioning.
Creating art and music, undertaking scientific discoveries, envisioning new worlds –
actual and fictional – does not rely on having to die in the
future. None of these activities even rely on the threat of
death. The immortal, indestructible robot, of course, might
not engage in precisely the same activities as we
do today. It would probably not need to worry about earning
its next meal by working for somebody else, but it could
still paint a painting, just because it would like to see
its mental processes – in this scenario, processes greatly
resembling our own – have some kind of external consequence
and embodiment in the external reality. Such external
embodiment is a vital component of flourishing.
Fear of death is not the sole
motivator for human action, nor the sole prerequisite for
value, as Ayn Rand acknowledged. There is more to life than
that. Life is not merely about survival and should be about
the pursuit of individual flourishing as well. Survival is a
necessary prerequisite, but, once it is achieved, an
individual is free to pursue higher-order values, such as
self-actualization. The individual would only be further
empowered in the quest for flourishing and
self-actualization in a hypothetical environment where no
threats to survival existed.
While we will never be true
immortal robots, such immortal robots could nonetheless
flourish and truly achieve life. As a result, the “immortal
robot” argument fails on multiple counts and is not a valid
challenge to indefinite life extension.
|
|
From the same author |
▪
The Imperative of Technological Progress: Why
Stagnation Will Necessarily Lead to Disaster and How
Techno-Optimism Can Overcome It
(no
334 – Sept. 15, 2015)
▪
Fast-Track Atheist Security Lanes and More: Time to
Jettison Perverse Egalitarianism
(no
333 – June 15, 2015)
▪
Universal Physical and Moral Laws, With No Lawgiver
(no
332 – May 15, 2015)
▪
The Ukrainian Regime's Censorship Spreads West to
Canada, and Political Correctness is to Blame
(no
331 – April 15, 2015)
▪
Review of Robert Wilfred Franson's The Shadow of
the Ship
(no
330 – March 15, 2015)
▪
More...
|
|
First written appearance of the
word 'liberty,' circa 2300 B.C. |
Le Québécois Libre
Promoting individual liberty, free markets and voluntary
cooperation since 1998.
|
|