Why Free-Market Advocates Are Not Obligated to Defend the
Economic Status Quo |
Many on the political left
today equate advocacy of free-market capitalism with an
“anything goes” support for the economic status quo. Many on
the political right give credence to this perception by,
indeed, seeking to defend the status quo just because it
happens to be so. Yet this is neither an obligatory nor an
advisable approach for characterizing a genuinely well-considered
free-market outlook.
Suppose that you are a
free-market advocate and also an engineer, well-versed in
the principles and methods for constructing durable, safe
structures. You hold that individuals and businesses should
have the freedom to be able to build structures which would
improve human well-being, in exchange for the opportunity to
earn a profit (or not, if they wish to build structures for
a charitable purpose). Now suppose that you are tasked with
evaluating the integrity of a particular structure
constructed by a private business – perhaps a bridge. This
particular bridge happens to be fully privately funded – no
subsidies, no exclusive rights, no barriers to competitors’
entry. The business undertaking the construction intends for
the bridge to be used as part of a major new toll road that
is intended to carry massive amounts of traffic.
Unfortunately, upon deploying
your technical skillset and studying the bridge design
carefully, you find that the bridge, while it is represented
as being able to withstand one thousand cars at a time,
would in fact collapse under the weight of only five hundred
cars. You also find that, in your basic repertoire of
engineering techniques, you have knowledge of construction
techniques and superior materials which would rectify these
design flaws and enable the bridge to be as safe and as
durable as originally represented. The trouble is that the
business owners want to hear none of it. They are attached
to their original design partly out of cost considerations,
but mostly because they simply cannot understand your
findings or appreciate their significance, no matter how
many different ways you have attempted to communicate them.
The business owners have almost no engineering knowledge
themselves and are generally contemptuous of overtly
mathematical, “nerdy” types (like you). They are skilled
salespeople who have capital from a previous venture and are
eager to make additional money on a high-profile project
such as this bridge. Suppose that you know that you have all
of the technical knowledge of your discipline firmly on your
side, but it is the owners’ money on the line, so,
unconvinced by your arguments, they build the bridge
according to their original specifications. They still
advertise it as highly durable, but in a sufficiently
nebulous way that the advertisements do not truly make any
specific promises or technical claims. (This business is
short on technically knowledgeable professionals, but spares
no expense in hiring attorneys to litigation-proof its
marketing materials.) The driving public’s impression from
the marketing campaign is expected to be, “It is an
incredibly sturdy, state-of-the-art, daring new bridge that
you will enjoy driving on in safety and style.” The business
owners contend that there is no problem. After all, were
this a truly free market, the public could choose to pay to
use their bridge or to find some alternative in getting from
point A to point B. And competitors could build their own
bridges, too, if they could buy the land, purchase the tools
and materials, and hire the labor to do it.
Of course, on most days, this
bridge would not collapse, since it is rare for
five hundred cars to be on it simultaneously. The owners
could well be reaping profits from their bridge for years
and convince the lay public to drive on it with no visible
ill consequences during that time. The bridge is,
however, vulnerable to high winds, earthquakes, freezing
damage, and gradual deterioration over time (exacerbated by
substandard construction). As time passes, the risks of
collapse increase. No bridge is invulnerable, but this
particular bridge is about 30 years farther along the path
to decay than other bridges that you know could easily have
been built in its place, had the owners only listened to
you. As a free-market advocate, you have some
sympathies with the owners’ view that the construction of
the bridge should not be forcibly prevented, as they are
using their own property for their own chosen purposes, and
they are not forcing anyone to use it. However, as an
engineer who knows better when it comes to quality of
bridge design and construction, what do you do?
This dilemma illustrates a
question at the core of how free-market advocates approach
the world in which they find themselves – a world, of
course, which is far from free in an economic sense, but
many people still use their own property for their own
purposes. There are some who will assert that the very fact
of private, voluntary use of property renders such use
inherently above criticism, provided it is a
manifestation of free choice. (We can overlook, for the sake
of this argument, the fact that, in the real world, many
incentives and constraints upon human action are routinely
distorted by the effects of political influences in favor of
one group or set of outcomes and/or in opposition to
others.) In this argument’s more typical instantiation in
today’s world, some would assert that any outcome
of “private enterprise” in today’s world must be acceptable
for free-market advocates, since it was (ostensibly)
somebody’s use of private property for a private purpose.
For example, mass corporate layoffs (virtually unheard of
until the 1970s), raising the price of a life-saving,
long-generic drug by 5,556 percent (as pharmaceutical
executive
Martin Shkreli did with Daraprim in 2015), listening to
or creating brutal “gangsta rap” (virtually unheard of until
the 1990s), teaching of creationism in private schools
(common throughout history, but increasingly untenable in
the face of over 150 years of mounting evidence), and many
other behaviors of questionable rationality and/or taste are
defended as being the decisions of private entities – so
what could be wrong about them?
|
“A free-market perspective is a political and economic position
which is compatible with completely rigorous, objective
views of matters of science, technology, mathematics,
history, metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, psychology, and
any other conceivable discipline.” |
The problem with reflexively
defending any and every behavior, just because a private
entity undertakes it, even in the absence of market
distortions, is that it misses an essential point. The
market is nothing more than the sum of the choices and
actions of its participants. A market outcome is not a
Panglossian “best of all possible worlds” scenario. Even in
the absence of compulsion or restraint, some people will be
mistaken, irrational, overconfident, immoral, confused, or
all of the above. Ex ante, they may expect that the
transactions and behaviors they engage in will benefit them
– much like a tribal shaman might believe that his rain
dance would bring forth water for the tribe’s crops – but,
ex post, they may well find themselves regretting
their behavior, or even if not, they may have still become
materially, intellectually, or emotionally worse off from it
compared to the alternatives. In addition to choice,
there is also truth – which comes in the form of
scientific, mathematical, historical, and philosophical
principles and facts. Truth is an outcome of combining
induction from the empirical facts of reality with
deduction from the application of logical reasoning to
known facts and incontrovertible first principles. It is
entirely possible for a person – including a wealthy,
powerful, influential person whose decisions affect
thousands or millions of others – to completely miss what
the truth is, or even to be ignorant of the correct methods
of arriving at the truth. In other words, if the external
reality is objective and governed by comprehensible natural
laws – and if morality is also objective in the sense that
some outcomes are incontrovertibly more beneficial to human
well-being than others – then it must be the case that
somebody who is thinking in a rational, well-informed manner
can truly “know better” than a particular decision-maker who
is not.
Does that mean that the market
could be replaced by some “superior” system of
decision-making? Ultimately, no. We have no guarantee that
any substitution of decision-making for that of private
actors could lead to a necessarily preferably
result from those decision makers’ free choices. If Person A
is irrational and mistaken, we have no guarantee that
leaving Person B in charge of A’s life would not lead to
even more irrational and mistaken choices,
compounded by the knowledge problem that B will necessarily
have in relation to A’s situation. The possibility that B
could be not simply misguided but nefarious, and seek to
sacrifice A’s genuine interests in favor of B’s own, is a
further argument against this kind of command-and-control
approach. More devastating, however, would be an outcome in
which a different person, C, really is doing his
best to act in a truthful, rational, and just manner, but
the controller B does not see it. Or perhaps B does
see it and thinks it is all well and good, but B needs to
set uniform standards that would keep the lowest common
denominator in check, and C’s scrupulous, innovative, and
principled way of living could never be generalized to a
society-wide system of controls.
But getting back to you, the
engineer: How to address the dilemma that you are in? Has
the “market” not “decided” that the bridge of substandard
technical quality is just fine? Not so fast. We must never
forget that we are the market, and that the market
does not only consist of the first decisions and
inclinations of some small group of wealthy, powerful, or
connected individuals. Quite the contrary: We are
what a truly free market consists of. A truly free market
consists not only of our affirmative choices, but also of
our negations and criticisms of certain
other choices. It consists of our knowledge, including those
situations where we truly “know better” than certain others.
You, the free-market engineer, could not force the bridge
owners to change their design. However, you could
fully publicize its flaws in a fully free society, one
characterized by robust protections of free speech and lack
of a climate of frivolous litigation with regard to libel
laws. If today such professional criticism is difficult, it
is because many larger, politically connected enterprises
will hire legions of attorneys to squelch sufficiently
specific assertions in meritless litigation that is too
costly for ordinary people to counter. But a truly free
society would lack this obstacle and would include a legal
system that is designed with speed, simplicity,
affordability, and protections for peaceful natural persons
in mind. A corporation would not be able to sue you for
publicizing detailed criticisms of its products; the judge
would be empowered to simply throw out such a lawsuit at
first glance. A truly free market of goods and ideas is not
an indiscriminate stew of anyone’s and everyone’s plans. Any
such plans also would get tested, scrutinized, refined, and
ultimately accepted or rejected by the other market
participants. To the extent that one owns property that
could sustain the perpetuation of a plan, one might counter
even strongly held prevailing opinions – but only
temporarily and only if one has other means of replenishing
that property if the plan causes it to be depleted.
Moreover, in a truly free
market, barriers to entry exist only on the basis of the
constraints of the physical world, not on politics and
special behind-the-scenes influence. Thus, competitors can
always arise with a superior business model. Perhaps if you,
the engineer, criticize the existing bridge sufficiently,
another business enterprise will learn of its defects,
purchase another piece of land, and construct a parallel,
sturdier bridge that takes your suggestions into account.
The misguided owners of the first bridge might eventually
find themselves out of business because travelers will
discover that safer, more convenient routes are available.
And if the bridge ever does fail, a free-market system of
civil liability will penalize those businesses who,
through negligence, failed to take reasonable precautions to
protect the health and safety of their customers. If the
bridge ever becomes an imminent danger to travelers, it
would be proper for public warnings to be issued and for the
law-enforcement entity (be it a minarchist government or a
private dispute-resolution agency) to order that traffic to
the bridge be discontinued until the immediate danger is
averted (perhaps through structural improvements at that
time). A free market does not permit the reckless
endangerment of unwitting, non-consenting others.
But always, in a hypothetical
free-market society or in our own, a free-market-oriented
engineer – or any professional, really – should have no
compunction about expressing the truth about the
soundness and validity of any party’s decisions or
proposals, be they private or governmental. Just as a
private party may well propose building a substandard
bridge, so might a government today actually develop a
decent bridge, especially if the incentives of a given
political system are conducive to that particular outcome.
The free-market engineer should not hesitate to praise the
technical design of a good bridge, no matter what its source
– because truth is true, and a bridge that could support
two thousand cars at a time would, indeed, support
those cars no matter who constructed it (provided the
methods and materials used are identical in each case). A
free-market perspective is a political and economic position
which is compatible with completely rigorous, objective
views of matters of science, technology, mathematics,
history, metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, psychology, and
any other conceivable discipline. Free-market advocates
should respect people’s right to make choices, even when
those choices are mistaken, but can maintain their own
right to criticize those mistakes using as high a set
of standards as they consider justified. If your values
include striving for truth and justice, then those values
are a part of the market as well, and you can improve market
outcomes by working to instantiate those values in reality.
|
|
From the same author |
▪
Refuting Ayn Rand's 'Immortal Robot' Argument
(no
337 – December 15, 2015)
▪
The Imperative of Technological Progress: Why
Stagnation Will Necessarily Lead to Disaster and How
Techno-Optimism Can Overcome It
(no
334 – Sept. 15, 2015)
▪
Fast-Track Atheist Security Lanes and More: Time to
Jettison Perverse Egalitarianism
(no
333 – June 15, 2015)
▪
Universal Physical and Moral Laws, With No Lawgiver
(no
332 – May 15, 2015)
▪
The Ukrainian Regime's Censorship Spreads West to
Canada, and Political Correctness is to Blame
(no
331 – April 15, 2015)
▪
More...
|
|
First written appearance of the
word 'liberty,' circa 2300 B.C. |
Le Québécois Libre
Promoting individual liberty, free markets and voluntary
cooperation since 1998.
|
|